•  64
    Reply to Crane, Jackson and McLaughlin (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 84 (1): 215-232. 2011.
  •  8
    The Debate about Mental Imagery
    Journal of Philosophy 81 (11): 678. 1984.
  • Forthcoming (b)" Externalism and Memory,"
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume. forthcoming.
  •  184
    On the possibility of disembodied existence
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61 (3): 275-282. 1983.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  191
    Pains and reasons: Why it is rational to kill the Messenger
    Philosophical Quarterly 64 (256): 423-433. 2014.
    In this paper, we defend the representationalist theory of phenomenal consciousness against a recent objection due to Hilla Jacobson, who charges representationalism with a failure to explain the role of pain in rationalizing certain forms of behavior. In rough outline, her objection is that the representationalist is unable to account for the rationality of certain acts, such as the act of taking pain killers, which are aimed at getting rid of the experience of pain rather than its intentional …Read more
  •  237
    Shoemaker’s The First-Person Perspective and Other Essays
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2): 461-464. 2000.
    This excellent collection of essays by Sydney Shoemaker covers his work over the last ten years in the philosophy of mind. Shoemaker's overarching concern in the collection is to provide an account of the mind that does justice to the “first-person perspective.” The two main topics are the nature of self-knowledge and the nature of sensory experience. The essays are insightful, careful, and thought-provoking.
  •  116
    Critical Notice
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 68 (1): 245-247. 2000.
    In 1995, in my book, Ten Problems of Consciousness, I proposed a version of the theory of phenomenal consciousness now known as representationalism. The present book, in part, consists of a further development of that theory along with replies to common objections. It is also concerned with two prominent challenges for any reductive theory of consciousness: the explanatory gap and the knowledge argument. In addition, it connects representationalism with two more general issues: the nature of col…Read more
  •  21
    What what it's like is really like
    Analysis 55 (2): 125. 1995.
  •  26
    Bergmann on the intentionality of thought
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 15 (3): 373-381. 1977.
  •  316
    Vague Objects
    Mind 99 (n/a): 535. 1990.
  •  1
    Nonconceptual content and fineness of grain
    In Tamar Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Perceptual Experience, Oxford University Press. 2006.
  •  19
    Review: Phenomenal Character and Color: Reply to Maund (review)
    Philosophical Studies 113 (3). 2003.
  •  256
    The picture theory of images
    Philosophical Review 97 (October): 497-520. 1988.
  •  149
    Qualia
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 1997.
    Feelings and experiences vary widely. For example, I run my fingers over sandpaper, smell a skunk, feel a sharp pain in my finger, seem to see bright purple, become extremely angry. In each of these cases, I am the subject of a mental state with a very distinctive subjective character. There is something it is like for me to undergo each state, some phenomenology that it has. Philosophers often use the term ‘qualia’ (singular ‘quale’) to refer to the introspectively accessible, phenomenal aspect…Read more
  •  80
    A causal analysis of seeing
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 42 (3): 311-325. 1982.
  •  83
    The Metaphysics of Mind
    Cambridge University Press. 1989.
    In this provocative book, Michael Tye presents his unique account of the metaphysical foundations of psychological discourse. In place of token identity theory or eliminative materialism, he advocates a generalisation of the adverbial approach to sensory experience, the 'operator theory'. He applies this to the analysis of prepositional attitudes, arguing that mental statements cannot involve reference to mental events or objects and that therefore causal statements about the mental cannot be re…Read more
  •  31
    In defense of the words 'human body'
    Philosophical Studies 38 (2). 1980.
  •  58
    Phenomenal Character and Color: Reply to Maund (review)
    Philosophical Studies 113 (3). 2003.
  •  49
    Externalism, twin earth, and self-knowledge
    with Brian P. McLaughlin
    In C. Macdonald, Peter K. Smith & C. Wright (eds.), Knowing Our Own Minds: Essays in Self-Knowledge, Oxford University Press. pp. 285--320. 1998.
  •  52
    A consideration of some of the most common questions about animal minds.Do birds have feelings? Can fish feel pain? Could a honeybee be anxious? For centuries, the question of whether or not animals are conscious like humans has prompted debates among philosophers and scientists. While most people gladly accept that complex mammals - such as dogs - share emotions and experiences with us, the matter of simpler creatures is much less clear. Meanwhile, the advent of the digital age and artificial i…Read more
  •  118
    Does Conscious Seeing Have A Finer Grain Than Attention?
    Thought: A Journal of Philosophy 3 (2): 154-158. 2014.
    Ned Block says ‘yes’ (, ). His position is based on the phenomenon of identity-crowding. According to Block, in cases of identity-crowding, something is consciously seen even though one cannot attend to it. In taking this view, Block is opposing a position I have taken in recent work (Tye 2009a, 2009b, 2010). He is also contributing to a vigorous recent debate in the philosophy of mind over the relation, if any, between consciousness and attention. Who is right? Not surprisingly, I think I am
  •  152
    Sorites paradoxes and the semantics of vagueness
    Philosophical Perspectives 8 189-206. 1994.
  •  175
    In Consciousness and Persons: Unity and Identity, Michael Tye takes on the thorny issue of the unity of consciousness and answers these important questions: What exactly is the unity of consciousness? Can a single person have a divided consciousness? What is a single person? Tye argues that unity is a fundamental part of human consciousness -- something so basic to everyday experience that it is easy to overlook. For example, when we hear the sound of waves crashing on a beach and at the same ti…Read more
  •  366
    Why the vague need not be higher-order vague
    Mind 103 (409): 43-45. 1994.
    Is higher-order vagueness a real phenomenon? Dominic Hyde (1994) claims that it is, and that it is part and parcel of vagueness itself. According to Hyde, any genuinely vague predicate must also be higher-order vague. His argument for this view is unsound, however. The purpose of this note is to expose the fallacy, and to make some related observations on the vague, the higher-order vague, and the vaguely vague.
  •  4
    Reply to Block, Jackson, and Shoemaker on Ten Problems of Consciousness
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (3). 1998.