•  30
    The Chain of Change (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 13 (1): 189-196. 1993.
  •  41
    Aristotle as Teacher: His Introduction to a Philosophical Science by Christopher Bruell
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 54 (1): 154-155. 2016.
    This commentary on Aristotle’s Metaphysics is in a style familiar from the writings of Leo Strauss and his students. The reader is presented with a paraphrase of the whole of Aristotle’s text, marked by seemingly odd omissions, emphases, and offhand remarks. One soon sees that the book is written in code. Only as the book progresses is the author more explicit concerning what he takes to be the main lines of Aristotle’s esoteric teaching, which is as follows.Aristotle writes the Metaphysics for …Read more
  •  38
    Aristotle described the scientific explanation of universal or general facts as deducing them through scientific demonstrations, that is, through syllogisms that met requirements he first formulated of logical validity and explanatoriness. In Chapters 19-23, he adds arguments for the further logical restrictions that scientific demonstrations can neither be indefinitely long nor infinitely extendible through the interposition of new middle terms. Chapters 24-26 argue for the superiority of unive…Read more
  •  5
    Inference from Signs (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 23 (2): 452-459. 2003.
  •  21
    Colloquium 3: Cosmic Orientation in Aristotle’s De Caelo
    Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium of Ancient Philosophy 26 (1): 91-129
    This paper examines how within De Caelo Aristotle argues that the heavens rotate to the right, because this is best. I isolate and evaluate its presuppositions and show how it comprises both a dialectical argument to cosmological principles and a partial demonstrative explanation on the basis of such principles. Second, I consider the expressions of epistemological hesitation that Aristotle offers in regard to this arguments, and draw conclusions concerning the status of cosmology as an Aristote…Read more
  •  36
    At Metaphysics A 5 986a22-b2, Aristotle refers to a Pythagorean table, with two columns of paired opposites. I argue that 1) although Burkert and Zhmud have argued otherwise, there is sufficient textual evidence to indicate that the table, or one much like it, is indeed of Pythagorean origin; 2) research in structural anthropology indicates that the tables are a formalization of arrays of “symbolic classification” which express a pre-scientific world view with social and ethical implications, ac…Read more
  •  48
    Aristotle on Homonymy (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 30 (1): 183-186. 2010.
  •  27
    Principles and Proofs (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 29 (2): 137-138. 1997.
  •  15
    Human Life and the Natural World: Readings in the History of Western Philosophy (edited book)
    with Patricia Kilroe
    Broadview Press. 1997.
    Human concern over the urgency of current environmental issues increasingly entails wide-ranging discussions of how we may rethink the relationship between humans and the rest of the natural world. In order to provide a context for such discussions this anthology provides a selection of some of the most important, interesting and influential readings on the subject from classical times through to the late nineteenth century. Included are such figures as Xenophon, Plato, Aristotle, Hildegard of B…Read more
  •  16
    To Tell the Truth: Dissoi Logoi 4 & Aristotle's Response
    In Alexander P. D. Mourelatos, Victor Miles Caston & Daniel W. Graham (eds.), Presocratic philosophy: essays in honour of Alexander Mourelatos, Ashgate. pp. 232-49. 2002.
  •  23
    Truth, etc (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 29 (2): 432-437. 2009.
  •  82
    Atoms, complexes, and demonstration: Posterior analytics 96b15-25
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 35 (4): 707-727. 2004.
    There is agreement neither concerning the point that is being made in Posterior analytics 96b15–25 nor the issue Aristotle intends to address. There are two major lines of interpretation of this passage. According to one, sketched by Themistius and developed by Philoponus and Eustratius, Aristotle is primarily concerned with determining the definitions of the infimae species that fall under a certain genus. They understand Aristotle as arguing that this requires collating definitional prediction…Read more
  •  53
  •  7
    Contrā Dale Jamieson, the study of the metaethical foundations of environmental ethics may well lead students to a more environmentally responsible way of life. For although metaethics is rarely decisive in decision making and action, there are two kinds of circumstances in which it can play a crucial role in our practical decisions. First, decisions that have unusual features do not summon habitual ethical reactions, and hence invite the application of ethical precepts that the study of metaeth…Read more
  •  38
    Tamir, Rawls, and the Temple Mount
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 22 (3). 2005.
    abstract What gives ethical and political validity to a state? This is to ask what a state is for and to provide a means to determine whether or not a constitution is just. In this paper I compare the account given by Tamir in Liberal Nationalism with that of Rawls, in order to clarify the decisive differences. Although both recognize the importance of particular associations and the moral imperative to be fair, Tamir places priority on the first and Rawls on the second. I explore their practica…Read more
  •  16
    Self, Sameness, and Soul in Alcibiades I_ and the _Timaeus
    Freiburger Zeitschrift für Philosophie Und Theologie 40 (1-2): 5-19. 1993.