•  24
    There are a growing number of general theories of contract law and of other doctrinal areas. These theories are vastly ambitious in their aims. This article explores the nature of these claims, and the motivations for offering such theories, while considering the challenges to success. It is in the nature of theorizing to seek general categories, including doctrinal categories, and to try to discover insights that hold across those categories. However, differences both within a doctrinal area an…Read more
  •  63
    On philosophy in american law : Analytical legal philosophy
    In Francis J. Mootz & William S. Boyd (eds.), On Philosophy in American Law, Cambridge University Press. 2009.
    This short article was written for a collection on American legal philosophy today. It gives a brief overview of analytical legal philosophy, and speculates on why this theoretical approach has been consistently misunderstood in the United States, from the time of the legal realists until today.
  •  90
    Law and Language: How Words Mislead Us
    Jurisprudence 1 (1): 25-38. 2010.
    Our world is full of fictional devices that let people feel better about their situation - through deception and self-deception. The legal realist, Felix Cohen, argued that law and legal reasoning is full of similarly dubious labels and bad reasoning, though of a special kind. He argued that judges, lawyers and legal commentators allow linguistic inventions and conventions to distort their thinking. Like the ancient peoples who built idols out of stone and wood and then asked them for assistance…Read more
  •  29
    Global Error and Legal Truth
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 29 (3): 535-547. 2009.
    One standard criterion for there being objectivity in an area of discourse is that there is conceptual space between what someone thinks to be the case and what actually is the case. That is, participants can be mistaken. This article explores one aspect of the objectivity debate as regards law: does it make sense to say that all legal officials or practitioners in a jurisdiction are mistaken (over a significant period of time) about some legal proposition? The possibility of legal error is impo…Read more
  •  83
    Contracts
    In Franklin G. Miller & Alan Wertheimer (eds.), The Ethics of Consent: Theory and Practice, Oxford University Press. 2010.
    Consent, in terms of voluntary choice, is - or, at least, appears to be or purports to be - at the essence of contract law. Contract law, both in principle and in practice, is about allowing parties to enter arrangements on terms they choose - each party imposing obligations on itself in return for obligations another party has placed upon itself. This freedom of contract- an ideal by which there are obligations to the extent, but only to the extent, freely chosen by the parties - is contrasted …Read more
  •  5
    The Idea of Private Law (review)
    Philosophical Books 37 (2): 131-132. 1996.
  • Reductionism and explanation in legal theory
    In James W. Harris, Timothy Andrew Orville Endicott, Joshua Getzler & Edwin Peel (eds.), Properties of Law: Essays in Honour of Jim Harris, Oxford University Press. 2006.
  •  220
    Legal positivism and 'explaining' normativity and authority
    American Philosophical Association Newsletter 5 (2 (Spring 2006)): 5-9. 2006.
    It has become increasingly common for legal positivist theorists to claim that the primary objective of legal theory in general, and legal positivism in particular, is "explaining normativity." The phrase "explaining normativity" can be understood either ambitiously or more modestly. The more modest meaning is an analytical exploration of what is meant by legal or moral obligation, or by the authority claims of legal officials. When the term is understood ambitiously - as meaning an explanation …Read more
  •  4
    JE Penner, The Idea of Property in Law (review)
    Philosophy in Review 18 (2): 143-145. 1998.
  •  97
    A number of important legal theorists have recently argued for metaphysically realist approaches to legal determinacy grounded in particular semantic theories or theories of reference, in particular, views of meaning and reference based on the works of Putnam and Kripke. The basic position of these theorists is that questions of legal interpretation and legal determinacy should be approached through semantic meaning. However, the role of authority (in the form of lawmaker choice) in law in gener…Read more
  • ADDIS, M.-Wittgenstein (review)
    Philosophical Books 41 (4): 267-268. 2000.
  •  14
    Review of Howard Schweber, The Language of Liberal Constitutionalism (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2008 (3). 2008.
  •  61
    Philosophy of law (edited book)
    Routledge. 2006.
    The first two volumes of the collection are devoted primarily to analytical legal theory--in particular, theories about the nature of law. This is the idea of legal philosophy most familiar to jurisprudential students in the English-speaking world, and many of the civil-law countries. The last two volumes sample schools and theorists who mostly come from outside the analytical tradition, and who are, in one sense or another, critical theorists--theorists more interested in offering systematic cr…Read more
  •  39
    John Austin
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2008.
  •  2
    Constitutions, originalism, and meaning
    In Grant Huscroft & Bradley W. Miller (eds.), The Challenge of Originalism: Essays in Constitutional Theory, Cambridge University Press. 2011.
  •  70
    A Dictionary of Legal Theory
    Oxford University Press. 2004.
    Modern legal theory contains a wide range of approaches and topics: from economic analysis of law to feminist legal theory to traditional analytical legal philosophy to a range of theories about justice. This healthy variety of jurisprudential work has created a problem: students and theorists working in one tradition may have difficulty understanding the concepts and terminology of a different tradition. This book works to make terminology and ways of thinking accessible. This dictionary covers…Read more
  •  55
    Legal philosophy in America
    In Cheryl Misak (ed.), The Oxford handbook of American philosophy, Oxford University Press. 2008.
    This article, written for the forthcoming Oxford Handbook of American Philosophy, offers an overview of the most important American contributions to legal philosophy - American legal realism, law and economics, various critical schools of jurisprudence, Lon Fuller, and Ronald Dworkin - while speculating on what might be distinctive of American legal philosophy. One obvious recurring theme is a focus on practical application in general, and adjudication (especially constitutional adjudication) in…Read more
  •  7
    Jurisprudence: theory and context
    Westview Press. 1996.
    Legal theory : problems and possibilities -- Individual theories about the nature of law -- Themes and principles -- Modern perspectives on legal theory.
  • Defeasibility and open texture
    In Jordi Ferrer Beltrán & Giovanni Battista Ratti (eds.), The Logic of Legal Requirements: Essays on Defeasibility, Oxford University Press. 2012.
  •  12
    Book reviews (review)
    Mind 102 (405): 193-195. 1993.
  •  59
    Raz on necessity
    Law and Philosophy 22 (6). 2003.
  •  5
    Philosophy of law (review)
    Philosophical Books 46 (1): 93-96. 2005.
  • Law, Language and Legal Determinacy
    Philosophical Quarterly 48 (192): 404-406. 1998.
  •  2
    John Austin and Constructing Theories of Law
    Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 24 (2): 431-440. 2011.
    One of the standard criticisms of John Austin’s work is that his portrayal of law, as essentially the command of a sovereign to its subjects, does not fit well with the way law is practiced or perceived by lawyers, judges, and citizens; and since the theory “fails to fit the facts,” Austin’s theory must be rejected in favor of later theories that have better fit. Many influential modern approaches to the nature of law, including Joseph Raz’s exclusive legal positivism and Ronald Dworkin’s interp…Read more
  •  95
    Conceptual Questions and Jurisprudence
    Legal Theory 1 (4): 465-479. 1995.
    Conceptual analysis is an integral part of legal theory, but the nature and purpose of such inquiries are often not clearly stated. In this article, I attempt to elaborate upon some of the differing reasons for conceptual analysis and what consequences may follow from choosing one objective rather than another. By showing that divergent purposes are often present in competing analyses of the same concept, I also hope to indicate why some “debates” in the jurisprudential literature are best under…Read more
  •  21
    A. D. Woozley and the Concept of Right Answers in Law
    Ratio Juris 5 (1): 58-66. 1992.
    Abstract.In the debates about legal determinacy, an important but often neglected issue is what is meant in the legal context by saying that a question has a right answer. By way of a critique of A. D. Woozley's discussion of “right answers,” I try to show how this issue is connected with issues of legal truth, legal mistake, and precedent.