•  24
    There are a growing number of general theories of contract law and of other doctrinal areas. These theories are vastly ambitious in their aims. This article explores the nature of these claims, and the motivations for offering such theories, while considering the challenges to success. It is in the nature of theorizing to seek general categories, including doctrinal categories, and to try to discover insights that hold across those categories. However, differences both within a doctrinal area an…Read more
  • Defeasibility and open texture
    In Jordi Ferrer Beltrán & Giovanni Battista Ratti (eds.), The Logic of Legal Requirements: Essays on Defeasibility, Oxford University Press. 2012.
  •  12
    Book reviews (review)
    Mind 102 (405): 193-195. 1993.
  •  59
    Raz on necessity
    Law and Philosophy 22 (6). 2003.
  •  5
    Philosophy of law (review)
    Philosophical Books 46 (1): 93-96. 2005.
  • Law, Language and Legal Determinacy
    Philosophical Quarterly 48 (192): 404-406. 1998.
  •  2
    John Austin and Constructing Theories of Law
    Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 24 (2): 431-440. 2011.
    One of the standard criticisms of John Austin’s work is that his portrayal of law, as essentially the command of a sovereign to its subjects, does not fit well with the way law is practiced or perceived by lawyers, judges, and citizens; and since the theory “fails to fit the facts,” Austin’s theory must be rejected in favor of later theories that have better fit. Many influential modern approaches to the nature of law, including Joseph Raz’s exclusive legal positivism and Ronald Dworkin’s interp…Read more
  •  95
    Conceptual Questions and Jurisprudence
    Legal Theory 1 (4): 465-479. 1995.
    Conceptual analysis is an integral part of legal theory, but the nature and purpose of such inquiries are often not clearly stated. In this article, I attempt to elaborate upon some of the differing reasons for conceptual analysis and what consequences may follow from choosing one objective rather than another. By showing that divergent purposes are often present in competing analyses of the same concept, I also hope to indicate why some “debates” in the jurisprudential literature are best under…Read more
  •  21
    A. D. Woozley and the Concept of Right Answers in Law
    Ratio Juris 5 (1): 58-66. 1992.
    Abstract.In the debates about legal determinacy, an important but often neglected issue is what is meant in the legal context by saying that a question has a right answer. By way of a critique of A. D. Woozley's discussion of “right answers,” I try to show how this issue is connected with issues of legal truth, legal mistake, and precedent.
  •  152
  •  104
    Jurisprudence: theory and context
    Westview Press. 1996.
    This introduction to legal theory provides a broad overview of the main topics and theories and covers the central issues. Written in a straightforward style, the author conveys academically challenging and often controversial ideas in a lucid manner.
  • Book Review (review)
    Law and Philosophy 32 (2-3): 327-331. 2013.
  •  30
    Teoría del Derecho: tipos y propósitos
    Isonomía. Revista de Teoría y Filosofía Del Derecho 25 57-68. 2006.
  • Physician-Assisted Suicide and Federalism
    Notre Dame Journal of Law, Ethics and Public Policy 17 (1): 53-70. 2003.
  •  106
    Legal positivism
    In Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson (eds.), The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory, Blackwell. 2004.
    This chapter contains section titled: History and Context Clarifications Alternative Legal Positivisms The Rule of Recognition and the Basic Norm The Divisions Within Contemporary Legal Positivism Debates and Distinctive Views Critiques of Legal Positivism Two Critics: Ronald Dworkin and John Finnis Methodological Questions and the Way Forward Conclusion Note References Further Reading.
  •  87
    There is an ongoing debate in the philosophical and jurisprudential literature regarding the nature and possibility of Contract theory. On one hand are those who argue (or assume) that there is, or should be, a single, general, universal theory of Contract Law, one applicable to all jurisdictions and all times. On the other hand are those who assert that Contract theory should be localized to particular times and places, perhaps even with different theories for different types of agreements. Thi…Read more
  •  104
    This article is based on a Lecture given as part of the Franklin J. Matchette Foundation Lecture Series on Truth at the Catholic University of America, School of Philosophy, in 2002. It explores what theorists in the natural law tradition and modern legal theorists have argued about what makes propositions of morality and law true, focusing on the rubric of "reason" as opposed to "will." It seems probable, and perhaps inevitable, that theorists about the nature of truth in morality must choose b…Read more
  •  84
    Analyzing law: new essays in legal theory (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 1998.
    Analyzing Law offers an important selection of the most influential and challenging work now being done in legal theory. A central focus of the essays in this work is the contribution of the well-known philosopher Jules Coleman to the various topics which are covered by the contributors.
  •  63
    On philosophy in american law : Analytical legal philosophy
    In Francis J. Mootz & William S. Boyd (eds.), On Philosophy in American Law, Cambridge University Press. 2009.
    This short article was written for a collection on American legal philosophy today. It gives a brief overview of analytical legal philosophy, and speculates on why this theoretical approach has been consistently misunderstood in the United States, from the time of the legal realists until today.
  •  90
    Law and Language: How Words Mislead Us
    Jurisprudence 1 (1): 25-38. 2010.
    Our world is full of fictional devices that let people feel better about their situation - through deception and self-deception. The legal realist, Felix Cohen, argued that law and legal reasoning is full of similarly dubious labels and bad reasoning, though of a special kind. He argued that judges, lawyers and legal commentators allow linguistic inventions and conventions to distort their thinking. Like the ancient peoples who built idols out of stone and wood and then asked them for assistance…Read more
  •  29
    Global Error and Legal Truth
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 29 (3): 535-547. 2009.
    One standard criterion for there being objectivity in an area of discourse is that there is conceptual space between what someone thinks to be the case and what actually is the case. That is, participants can be mistaken. This article explores one aspect of the objectivity debate as regards law: does it make sense to say that all legal officials or practitioners in a jurisdiction are mistaken (over a significant period of time) about some legal proposition? The possibility of legal error is impo…Read more
  •  83
    Contracts
    In Franklin G. Miller & Alan Wertheimer (eds.), The Ethics of Consent: Theory and Practice, Oxford University Press. 2010.
    Consent, in terms of voluntary choice, is - or, at least, appears to be or purports to be - at the essence of contract law. Contract law, both in principle and in practice, is about allowing parties to enter arrangements on terms they choose - each party imposing obligations on itself in return for obligations another party has placed upon itself. This freedom of contract- an ideal by which there are obligations to the extent, but only to the extent, freely chosen by the parties - is contrasted …Read more
  •  5
    The Idea of Private Law (review)
    Philosophical Books 37 (2): 131-132. 1996.
  • Reductionism and explanation in legal theory
    In James W. Harris, Timothy Andrew Orville Endicott, Joshua Getzler & Edwin Peel (eds.), Properties of Law: Essays in Honour of Jim Harris, Oxford University Press. 2006.
  •  220
    Legal positivism and 'explaining' normativity and authority
    American Philosophical Association Newsletter 5 (2 (Spring 2006)): 5-9. 2006.
    It has become increasingly common for legal positivist theorists to claim that the primary objective of legal theory in general, and legal positivism in particular, is "explaining normativity." The phrase "explaining normativity" can be understood either ambitiously or more modestly. The more modest meaning is an analytical exploration of what is meant by legal or moral obligation, or by the authority claims of legal officials. When the term is understood ambitiously - as meaning an explanation …Read more