•  316
    Deciding how to decide
    In Garrett Cullity & Berys Nigel Gaut (eds.), Ethics and practical reason, Oxford University Press. pp. 29--52. 1997.
  •  308
    of (from Philosophy Papers Online)
  •  302
    Derek Parfit finally meets the Buddha -- on Tralfamadore! This paper is also archived at SSRN
  •  282
    The Possibility of Practical Reason
    Oxford University Press. 2000.
    Suppose that we want to frame a conception of reasons that isn't relativized to the inclinations of particular agents. That is, we want to identify particular things that count as reasons for acting simpliciter and not merely as reasons for some agents rather than others, depending on their inclinations. One way to frame such a conception is to name some features that an action can have and to say that they count as reasons for someone whether or not he is inclined to care about them. The proble…Read more
  •  243
    Foundations for Moral Relativism
    OpenBook Publishers. 2013.
    In Foundations for Moral Relativism, J. David Velleman shows that different communities can indeed be subject to incompatible moralities, because their local mores are rationally binding. At the same time, he explains why the mores of different communities, even when incompatible, are still variations on the same moral themes. The book thus maps out a universe of many moral worlds without, as Velleman puts it, "moral black holes”. The five self-standing chapters discuss such diverse topics as on…Read more
  •  231
    Practical reflection
    Philosophical Review 94 (1): 33-61. 1985.
    “What do you see when you look at your face in the mirror?” asks J. David Velleman in introducing his philosophical theory of action. He takes this simple act of self-scrutiny as a model for the reflective reasoning of rational agents: our efforts to understand our existence and conduct are aided by our efforts to make it intelligible. Reflective reasoning, Velleman argues, constitutes practical reasoning. By applying this conception, _Practical Reflection_ develops philosophical accounts of int…Read more
  •  205
    Doables
    Philosophical Explorations (1): 1-16. 2013.
    Just as our scientific inquiries are framed by our prior conception of what can be observed ? that is, of observables ? so our practical deliberations are framed by our prior conception of what can be done, that is, of doables. And doables are socially constructed, with the result that they vary between societies. I explore how doables are constructed and conclude with some remarks about the implications for moral relativism.
  •  192
    Self to Self
    Philosophical Review 105 (1): 39-76. 1996.
    Images of myself being Napoleon can scarcely merely be images of the physical figure of Napoleon.... They will rather be images of, for instance, the desolation at Austerlitz as viewed by me vaguely aware of my short stature and my cockaded hat, my hand in my tunic.
  •  169
    Précis of The Possibility of Practical Reason
    Philosophical Studies 121 (3). 2004.
  •  166
    II. The Gift of Life
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 36 (3): 245-266. 2008.
    No Abstract
  •  150
    Dying
    Think 11 (32): 29-32. 2012.
    Some people hope to die in their sleep. Not me. I don't regret having been oblivious at my birth, but I don't want death to catch me napping
  •  146
  •  114
    Self to Self: Selected Essays
    Cambridge University Press. 2005.
    Self to Self brings together essays on personal identity, autonomy, and moral emotions by the distinguished philosopher J. David Velleman. Although each of the essays was written as an independent piece, they are unified by an overarching thesis, that there is no single entity denoted by 'the self', as well as by themes from Kantian ethics, psychoanalytic theory, social psychology, and Velleman's work in the philosophy of action. Two of the essays were selected by the editors of Philosophers' An…Read more
  •  113
    XIV. Don't Worry, Feel Guilty
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 52 235-248. 2003.
    One can feel guilty without thinking that one actually is guilty of moral wrongdoing. For example, one can feel guilty about eating an ice cream or skipping aerobics, even if one doesn't take a moralistic view of self-indulgence. And one can feel guilty about things that aren't one's doing at all, as in the case of survivor's guilt about being spared some catastrophe suffered by others. Guilt without perceived wrongdoing may of course be irrational, but I think it is sometimes rational, and I wa…Read more
  •  101
    On Being Me: A Personal Invitation to Philosophy
    Princeton University Press. 2020.
    A moral philosopher’s meditations on some of life’s most important questions We’ve all had to puzzle over such profound matters as birth, death, regret, free will, agency, and love. How might philosophy help us think through these vital concerns? In On Being Me, renowned moral philosopher J. David Velleman presents a concise, accessible, and intimate exploration into subjects that we care deeply about, offering compelling insights into what it means to be human. Each of Velleman’s short, persona…Read more
  •  95
    Brandt's definition of "good"
    Philosophical Review 97 (3): 353-371. 1988.
  •  88
  •  84
    Comments on John Martin Fischer’s Our Stories (review)
    Philosophical Studies 158 (3): 515-521. 2012.
    I comment on the three main themes in Our Stories: the harm of death, the narrative structure of life, and the value of immortality. I begin with a subsidiary theme, namely, the use of narrative examples in philosophy.
  •  83
    Konrad Morgen: The Conscience of a Nazi Judge recounts the wartime career of Georg Konrad Morgen (1909–1982), a judge who prosecuted crimes committed by members of the SS in Nazi concentration camps, including Buchenwald, Dachau, and Auschwitz. In 1943, Morgen discovered the existence of gas chambers at Auschwitz-Birkenau. He tried to throw sand in the works by prosecuting concentration camp officials for lesser crimes. He charged the chief of the Auschwitz Gestapo with for 2,000 murders, and ev…Read more
  •  69
    Narrative Explanation
    Philosophical Review 112 (1): 1-25. 2003.
    A story does more than recount events; it recounts events in a way that renders them intelligible, thus conveying not just information but also understanding. We might therefore be tempted to describe narrative as a genre of explanation. When the police invite a suspect to “tell his story,” they are asking him to explain the blood on his shirt or his absence from home on the night of the murder; and whether he is judged to have a “good story” will depend on its adequacy as an explanation. Can we…Read more
  •  61
    I. The Identity Problem
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 36 (3): 221-244. 2008.
  •  61
    Reply to Catriona MacKenzie
    Philosophical Explorations 10 (3). 2007.
    In her excellent critique of my book Self to Self (2006), Catriona Mackenzie highlights three gaps in my view of the self. First, my effort to distinguish among different applications of the concept 'self' is not matched by any attempt to explain the interactions among the selves so distinguished. Second, in analyzing practical reasoning as aimed at self-understanding, I speak sometimes of causal-psychological understanding (e.g. in the paper titled 'The Centered Self') and sometimes of narrativ…Read more
  •  55
    Review of Faces of Intention by Michael Bratman (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 51 (202). 2001.
  •  50
    Michael Bratman’s planning, time, and self-governance
    Tandf: Inquiry 1-13. forthcoming.
    .
  •  46
    Willing the Law J. David Velleman
    In Peter Baumann & Monika Betzler (eds.), Practical Conflicts: New Philosophical Essays, Cambridge University Press. pp. 27. 2004.
  •  40
    New model publishing
    The Philosophers' Magazine 14 (14): 11-12. 2001.
  •  35
    Review: Replies to Discussion on "The Possibility of Practical Reason" (review)
    Philosophical Studies 121 (3). 2004.