•  8
    Rule Consistency
    Law and Philosophy 19 (3): 369-390. 2000.
    This paper develops the theory that a set ofrules is consistent if it is not possible that (1)the conditions of the rules in the set are allsatisfied, (2) there is no exception to either one ofthe rules, and (3) the consequences of the rules areincompatible. To this purpose the notion ofconsistency is generalised to make it cover rulesand is relativised to some background of constraints.This theory is formalised by means of Rule Logic, inwhich rules are treated as constraints on thepossible worl…Read more
  •  26
    Law and Coherence
    Ratio Juris 17 (1): 87-105. 2004.
    This paper deals with the questions of whether the law should be coherent and what this coherence would amount to. In this connection so‐called “integrated coherentism” is introduced. According to integrated coherentism, an acceptance set is coherent if and only if it contains everything that should rationally be accepted according to what else one accepts and does not contain anything that should rationally be rejected according to what else one accepts. Such an acceptance set is ideally a theo…Read more
  • De betekenis van juridische statuswoorden
    Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy 37 (1): 13-28. 2008.
  • Legal Reductionism and Freedom (review)
    Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy 2 166-170. 2003.
  •  19
    Elusive normativity
    Netherlands Journal of Legal Philosophy 40 (2): 146-168. 2011.
  •  46
    Rule-applying legal arguments are traditionally treated as a kind of syllogism. Such a treatment overlooks the fact that legal principles and rules are not statements which describe the world, but rather means by which humans impose structure on the world. Legal rules create legal consequences, they do not describe them. This has consequences for the logic of rule- and principle-applying arguments, the most important of which may be that such arguments are defeasible. This book offers an extensi…Read more
  •  114
    Law and defeasibility
    Artificial Intelligence and Law 11 (2-3): 221-243. 2003.
    The paper consists of three parts. In the first part five kinds of defeasibility are distinguished that is ontological, conceptual, epistemic, justification and logical defeasibility. In the second part it is argued that from these, justification defeat is the phenomenon that plays a role in legal reasoning. In the third part, the view is defended that non-monotonic logics are not necessary to model justification defeat, but that they are so to speak the natural way to model this phenomenon.
  •  79
    Dialectical models in artificial intelligence and law
    Artificial Intelligence and Law 8 (2-3): 137-172. 2000.
    Dialogues and dialectics have come to playan important role in the field of ArtificialIntelligence and Law. This paper describes thelegal-theoretical and logical background of this role,and discusses the different services into whichdialogues are put. These services include:characterising logical operators, modelling thedefeasibility of legal reasoning, providing the basisfor legal justification and identifying legal issues,and establishing the law in concrete cases. Specialattention is given to…Read more
  •  18
    Legal Knowledge about What?
    with Aleksander Peczenik
    Ratio Juris 13 (3): 326-345. 2000.
    We assume—in contrast to many “legal realists”—that law is a part of reality. Law exists because people believe in law, but law is not identical with beliefs. Law supervenes on human beliefs, preferences, actions, dispositions and artefacts. Moreover, the morally binding personal interpretation of the law supervenes on two things together: on the individual's knowledge of legal institutions and on moral obligation. The first supervenes in its turn on mutual beliefs; the second supervenes on moti…Read more
  •  18
    Preface
    Artificial Intelligence and Law 11 (2-3): 77-79. 2003.
    The paper consists of three parts. In the first part five kinds of defeasibility are distinguished that is ontological, conceptual, epistemic, justification and logical defeasibility. In the second part it is argued that from these, justification defeat is the phenomenon that plays a role in legal reasoning. In the third part, the view is defended that non-monotonic logics are not necessary to model justification defeat, but that they are so to speak the natural way to model this phenomenon.
  •  29
    Introduction. Papers from the jurix '95 conference
    Artificial Intelligence and Law 5 (4): 243-248. 1997.
  •  33
    Comparing alternatives in the law
    Artificial Intelligence and Law 12 (3): 181-225. 2004.
    This paper argues the thesis that a particular style of reasoning, qualitative comparative reasoning (QCR), plays a role in at least three areas of legal reasoning that are central in AI and law research, namely legal theory construction, case-based reasoning in the form of case comparison, and legal proof. The paper gives an informal exposition of one particular way to deal with QCR, based on the author’s previous work on reason-based logic (RBL). Then it contains a substantially adapted formal…Read more
  •  20
    Anything Goes: An Apology for Parallel Distributed Legal Science
    Informal Logic 36 (3): 271-287. 2016.
    Doctrinal legal science seems to lack a proper method and purpose. This interpretation clarifies its value. The backbone of the argu- ment consists of two theses. The first is that coherence—in a sense unusu- al in law—plays a crucial role in legal science. The second is that doctrinal legal science is a social enterprise and this should be consid- ered in attempts to understand it. Based on these, a picture of doctrinal legal science is given consisting of parallel distributed constructions of …Read more
  •  29
    A model of juridical acts: part 1: the world of law (review)
    Artificial Intelligence and Law 19 (1): 23-48. 2011.
    This paper aims at providing an account of juridical acts that forms a suitable starting point for the creation of computational systems that deal with juridical acts. The paper is divided into two parts. Because juridical acts will be analyzed as intentional changes in the world of law, the ‘furniture’ of this world, that consists broadly speaking of entities, facts and rules, plays a central role in the analysis. This first part of the paper deals with this furniture and its philosophical unde…Read more
  •  146
    A theory of legal reasoning and a logic to match
    Artificial Intelligence and Law 4 (3-4): 199-273. 1996.
    This paper describes a model of legal reasoning and a logic for reasoning with rules, principles and goals that is especially suited to this model of legal reasoning. The paper consists of three parts. The first part describes a model of legal reasoning based on a two-layered view of the law. The first layer consists of principles and goals that express fundamental ideas of a legal system. The second layer contains legal rules which in a sense summarise the outcome of the interaction of the prin…Read more
  •  26
    A model of juridical acts: part 2: the operation of juridical acts (review)
    Artificial Intelligence and Law 19 (1): 49-73. 2011.
    This paper aims at providing an account of juridical acts that forms a suitable starting point for the creation of computational systems that deal with juridical acts. The paper is divided into two parts. This second part of the paper deals in some detail with the operation of juridical acts. Topics dealt with include: power and competence, capacity, form requirements, partial validity, avoidance and representation
  •  27
    Book review (review)
    Artificial Intelligence and Law 2 (4): 315-323. 1993.
  •  25
    Introduction to the special issue on machine law
    with Bartosz Brożek and Bipin Indurkhya
    Artificial Intelligence and Law 25 (3): 251-253. 2017.