Julia Driver

University of Texas at Austin
University of St. Andrews
Johns Hopkins University
Department of Philosophy
PhD
Austin, Texas, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
Value Theory
Meta-Ethics
Normative Ethics
Areas of Interest
Value Theory
  •  116
    Pleasure as the standard of virtue in Hume's moral philosophy
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 85 (2). 2004.
    But in many orders of beauty, particularly those of the finer arts, it is requisite to employ much reasoning, in order to feel the proper sentiment; and a false relish may frequently be corrected by argument and reflection. There are just grounds to conclude, that moral beauty partakes much of this latter species, and demands the assistance of our intellectual faculties, in order to give it a suitable influence on the human mind (EPM, 173)
  •  57
    On 'What makes killing wrong?'
    Journal of Medical Ethics 39 (1): 8-8. 2013.
    Walter Sinnott-Armstrong and Franklin Miller1 make a convincing case for their claim that what is wrong about killing someone is that one is putting the person in a state of universal and irreversible disability. Thus, killing in and of itself is not an additional harm for a person who has been universally and irreversibly disabled. The implications for such a view are, as they note, quite wide-ranging. Given advances in medical technology, there are individuals being kept alive now who are univ…Read more
  •  101
    Gertrude Elizabeth Margaret Anscombe
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2009.
  •  4
    Normative ethics
    In Frank Jackson & Michael Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Contemporary Philosophy, Oxford University Press. 2005.
  • HARRIS, GW-Agent-Centered Morality
    Philosophical Books 42 (3): 217-219. 2001.
  •  30
    Moralism
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 22 (2): 137-151. 2005.
    abstract In this paper moralism is defined as the illicit use of moral considerations. Three different varieties of moralism are then discussed — moral absolutism, excessive standards and demandingness, and presenting non‐moral considerations as moral ones. Both individuals and theories can be regarded as moralistic in some of these senses. Indeed, some critics of consequentialism have regarded that theory as moralistic. The author then describes the problems associated with each sense of ‘moral…Read more
  •  177
    Dream immorality
    Philosophy 82 (1): 5-22. 2007.
    This paper focuses on an underappreciated issue that dreams raise for moral evaluation: is immorality possible in dreams? The evaluatiotial internalist is committed to answering ‘yes.’ This is because the internalist account of moral evaluation holds that the moral quality of a person's actions, what a person does, her agency in any given case is completely determined by factors that are internal to that agency, such as the person's motives and/or intentions. Actual production of either good or …Read more
  •  32
    Metaquestions
    Noûs 18 (2): 299-309. 1984.
  •  89
    Private Blame
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (2): 215-220. 2016.
    This paper explores a problem for Michael McKenna’s conversation model of moral responsibility that views blame as characteristically part of a conversational exchange. The problem for this model on which this paper focuses is the problem of private blame. Sometimes when we blame we do so without any intention to engage in a communicative exchange. It is argued that McKenna’s model cannot adequately account for private blame.
  •  2
    Luck and Fortune in Moral Evaluation
    In Martijn Blaauw (ed.), Contrastivism in philosophy, Routledge/taylor & Francis Group. 2013.
  •  163
    The Conflation of Moral and Epistemic Virtue
    Metaphilosophy 34 (3): 367-383. 2003.
    Accounts of virtue suffer a conflation problem when they appear unable to preserve intuitive distinctions between types of virtue. In this essay I argue that a number of influential attempts to preserve the distinction between moral and epistemic virtues fail, on the grounds that they characterize virtuous traits in terms of ‘characteristic motivation’. I claim that this does not distinguish virtuous traits at the level of value‐conferring quality, and I propose that the best alternative is to d…Read more
  •  82
    Hyperactive ethics
    Philosophical Quarterly 44 (174): 9-25. 1994.
  •  306
    Uneasy Virtue
    Cambridge University Press. 2001.
    The predominant view of moral virtue can be traced back to Aristotle. He believed that moral virtue must involve intellectual excellence. To have moral virtue one must have practical wisdom - the ability to deliberate well and to see what is morally relevant in a given context. Julia Driver challenges this classical theory of virtue, arguing that it fails to take into account virtues which do seem to involve ignorance or epistemic defect. Some 'virtues of ignorance' are counterexamples to accoun…Read more
  •  67
    Consequentialism and Feminist Ethics
    Hypatia 20 (4): 183-199. 2000.
    This essay attempts to show that sophisticated consequentialism is able to accommodate the concerns that have traditionally been raised by feminist writers in ethics. Those concerns have primarily to do with the fact that consequentialism is seen as both too demanding of the individual and neglectful of the agent's special obligations to family and friends. Here, I argue that instrumental justification for partiality can be provided, for example, even though an attitude of partiality is not char…Read more
  •  10
    The Practice of Moral Judgment
    Philosophical Books 35 (2): 106-108. 1994.
  •  43
    An Introduction to Kant'S Ethics
    Philosophical Books 37 (4): 258-260. 1996.
  •  33
    Review of Brad Hooker, Ideal Code, Real World (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2002 (6). 2002.
  •  96
    Moral sense and sentimentalism
    In Roger Crisp (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the History of Ethics, Oxford University Press. pp. 358. 2013.
    This chapter focuses on sentimentalism – the view that morality is based on sentiment – in particular, the sentiment of sympathy. Sentimentalism was historically articulated in opposition to two positions: Hobbesian egoism, in which morality is based on self-interest; and Moral Rationalism, which held that morality is based on reason alone. The Sentimentalists challenged both views, arguing that there is more to what motivates human beings than simple self-interest and that reason alone is insuf…Read more
  •  13
    Knowing Better by Daniel Star
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 93 (3): 713-719. 2016.
  •  52
    Introduction
    Utilitas 13 (2): 137. 2001.
    The evaluation of character has taken on new significance in moral theory, and, indeed, some advocate a shift in focus away from evaluating action to evaluating character. This has been taken to pose special challenges for utilitarian and consequentialist moral theory. Utilitarianism's commitment to impartiality and its seeming failure to accommodate virtue evaluation have led to problems, some of which are developed in the essays in this volume
  •  32
    Caesar's Wife: On the Moral Significance of Appearing Good
    Journal of Philosophy 89 (7): 331. 1992.
  •  96
    The Secret Chain: A Limited Defense of Sympathy
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 49 (s1): 234-238. 2011.
    This paper responds to criticisms of sympathy-based approaches to ethics made by Jesse Prinz, focusing on the criticism that emotions are too variable to form a basis for ethics. I draw on the idea, articulated by early sentimentalists such as Hutcheson and Hume, that proper reliance on sympathy is subject to a corrective procedure in order, in part, to avoid the variability problem.
  •  74
    The ethics of intervention
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (4): 851-870. 1997.
    This essay explores the obligations that may arise from benevolently intended interventions that go awry. The author argues that even when the intervening agent has acted with good intentions and in a non-negligent manner, she may be required to continue aid in cases where her initial intervention failed. This is surprising because it means that persons who perform supererogatory acts run the risk of incurring additional heavy obligations through no fault of their own. The author also considers …Read more
  •  147
    Moralism
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 22 (2). 2005.
    abstract In this paper moralism is defined as the illicit use of moral considerations. Three different varieties of moralism are then discussed — moral absolutism, excessive standards and demandingness, and presenting non‐moral considerations as moral ones. Both individuals and theories can be regarded as moralistic in some of these senses. Indeed, some critics of consequentialism have regarded that theory as moralistic. The author then describes the problems associated with each sense of ‘moral…Read more