•  5
    Praenomen Petronii: The Date And Author Of The Satyricon Reconsidered
    with Dirk Rohmann
    Classical Quarterly 61 (2): 660-676. 2011.
  •  23
    Creative Communication Through the Nonverbal Experience
    Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 7 (3): 30-31. 1991.
  •  37
    Using the Case Study Method to Teach Interpersonal Communication
    with Marjorie C. Feinstein
    Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 9 (3): 11-14. 1992.
  •  17
    Feinstein/Veenendall, from page 14
    with Marjorie C. Feinstein
    Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines 9 (3): 26-26. 1992.
  •  40
    Color in Reference Production: The Role of Color Similarity and Color Codability
    with Jette Viethen, Martijn Goudbeek, and Emiel Krahmer
    Cognitive Science 41 (S6): 1493-1514. 2017.
    It has often been observed that color is a highly preferred attribute for use in distinguishing descriptions, that is, referring expressions produced with the purpose of identifying an object within a visual scene. However, most of these observations were based on visual displays containing only colors that were maximally different in hue and for which the language of experimentation possessed basic color terms. The experiments described in this paper investigate whether speakers’ preference for…Read more
  •  44
    A Way to Interpret Łukasiewicz Logic and Basic Logic
    Studia Logica 90 (3): 407-423. 2008.
    Fuzzy logics are in most cases based on an ad-hoc decision about the interpretation of the conjunction. If they are useful or not can typically be found out only by testing them with example data. Why we should use a specific fuzzy logic can in general not be made plausible. Since the difficulties arise from the use of additional, unmotivated structure with which the set of truth values is endowed, the only way to base fuzzy logics on firm ground is the development of alternative semantics to al…Read more
  • Literary Mediation of Knowledge and Biblical Studies
    Nova et Vetera 4 761-786. 2006.
  • Yogic Experience under Scientific Research
    Journal of Dharma 4 (1): 29-38. 1979.
  • Tomorrow's Society
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 40 (2): 300-301. 1979.
  •  6
    Bd. 1. 17. und 18. Jahrhundert (Text 1-21) -- Bd. 2. 19. und 20. Jahrhundert (Text 22-41).
  •  6
    Planning and Political Economy
    Social Research: An International Quarterly 50. 1983.
  •  20
    Notes on Antoine de la Sale's Reconfort de Mme du Fresne
    Mediaeval Studies 37 (1): 478-493. 1975.
  •  18
    Suppression of feeding by intrahypothalamic implants of estradiol in male and female rats
    with William W. Beatty and Dennis A. O’Briant
    Bulletin of the Psychonomic Society 3 (4): 273-274. 1974.
  • Radical Orthodoxy: Une première impression
    Revue Thomiste 101 (3): 409-444. 2001.
  •  1
    Y at-il une herméneutique thomiste?
    Revue Thomiste 104 (1-2): 273-318. 2004.
  •  74
    Logics designed to deal with vague statements typically allow algebraic semantics such that propositions are interpreted by elements of residuated lattices. The structure of these algebras is in general still unknown, and in the cases that a detailed description is available, to understand its significance for logics can be difficult. So the question seems interesting under which circumstances residuated lattices arise from simpler algebras in some natural way. A possible construction is describ…Read more
  •  40
    Partial algebras for Łukasiewicz logics and its extensions
    Archive for Mathematical Logic 44 (7): 913-933. 2005.
    It is a well-known fact that MV-algebras, the algebraic counterpart of Łukasiewicz logic, correspond to a certain type of partial algebras: lattice-ordered effect algebras fulfilling the Riesz decomposition property. The latter are based on a partial, but cancellative addition, and we may construct from them the representing ℓ-groups in a straightforward manner. In this paper, we consider several logics differing from Łukasiewicz logics in that they contain further connectives: the PŁ-, PŁ'-, PŁ…Read more
  •  24
    Plotin considère parfois l’intellection comme une sorte de sensation, alors qu’il distingue par ailleurs fortement les deux activités. Le but de cet article est d’étudier cette description qui semble paradoxale dans la mesure où l’intellection est ramenée à un processus auquel elle est opposée en même temps. Nous devons tout d’abord mettre en lumière le lien entre la sensation et l’intellection. Il est ensuite nécessaire de montrer de quelle manière la sensation est considérée comme un modèle qu…Read more
  •  29
    De Descartes ą Athikté: métamorphoses du sensible chez Valéry
    Aisthesis: Pratiche, Linguaggi E Saperi Dell’Estetico 5 (1). 2012.
    In this contribution, we shall examine how Valéry leaves Descartes, and the paradigm of sight, in favor of the dancer Athiktè, typical of the paradigm of hearing and touch. If Descartes offers the pattern of an analytic mapping, that method reveals itself irrelevant to take into account what Valéry calls the C.E.M (Corps Esprit Monde). On the other side, a dancer, like Athiktè appears as the model of poiesis, showing the natura naturans in progress
  •  29
    Body-Mind Aporia in the Seizure of Othello
    Philosophy and Literature 36 (1): 183-186. 2012.
    One of the most curious events in Othello is the titular character’s epileptic fit, which does not appear in the story by Cinthio that is the accepted source of the play’s plot. Why does Shakespeare invent such an incident? The easiest direction to take is the equation of epilepsy with demonic possession, a common belief in the early modern period. In this essay, however, I argue from textual and critical evidence for a philosophical interpretation of Othello’s epilepsy: namely, that his seizure…Read more
  •  55
    Praenomen petronii: The date and author of the satyricon reconsidered
    with Dirk Rohmann
    Classical Quarterly 61 (2): 660-676. 2011.