•  4
    Poznámka k „Platónovi“
    Ostium 1 (2). 2005.
  •  2
    Augustínove pragmatické paradoxy
    Ostium 4 (4). 2008.
  •  1
    Hegelov svet protirečení
    Ostium 4 (2). 2008.
  • Quinov otáznik
    Ostium 3 (2). 2007.
  •  3
    Ockham a insolunilia 1
    Ostium 2 (4). 2006.
  •  36
    Stealing Harman’s Thought: knowledge saboteurs and dogmatists
    Synthese 198 (Suppl 7): 1787-1799. 2018.
    You receive a pink packet from Miss Lead, a notoriously deceptive truth-teller. You know that if you open the packet and do not find blank pages, then you will justifiably change your mind about the evidence being misleading. Indeed, you will infer that your previous fears about misleading evidence were themselves founded on misleading evidence. Should you open the pink packet? No, answers an advocate of self-censorship. Yes, answers an advocate of the principle that you should base conclusions …Read more
  •  31
    Other‐Centric Reasoning
    Metaphilosophy 49 (4): 489-509. 2018.
    This article considers question‐begging's opposite fallacy. Instead of relying on my beliefs for my premises when I should be using my adversary's beliefs, I rely on my adversary's beliefs when I should rely on my own. Just as question‐begging emerges from egocentrism, its opposite emerges from other‐centrism. Stepping into the other person's shoes is an effective strategy for understanding him. But you must return to your own shoes when forming your beliefs. Evidence is agent centered. Other‐ce…Read more
  •  10
    Was Descartes's cogito a diagonal deduction?
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (3): 346-351. 1986.
    Peter Slezak and William Boos have independently advanced a novel interpretation of Descartes's "cogito". The interpretation portrays the "cogito" as a diagonal deduction and emphasizes its resemblance to Godel's theorem and the Liar. I object that this approach is flawed by the fact that it assigns 'Buridan sentences' a legitimate role in Descartes's philosophy. The paradoxical nature of these sentences would have the peculiar result of undermining Descartes's "cogito" while enabling him to "di…Read more
  • The Wonder of Armchair Inquiry
    In Thought experiments, Oxford University Press. 1992.
    This chapter focuses on armchair inquiry. Thought experiment has the feel of clairvoyance, thus eliciting awe in some and suspicion in others. But the wonder of thought experiment is just a special case of our vague puzzlement about how a question could be answered by merely thinking. There is no mystery when investigators look, measure, and manipulate. Their answers come from the news borne by observation and experiment. But if you just ponder, then the information you have leaving the armchair…Read more
  • This chapter lays out a classification scheme for thought experiments. A good scheme consolidates knowledge in a way that minimizes the demand on your memory and expedites the acquisition of new knowledge by raising helpful leading questions. Thought experiments are all reducible to two highly specific forms of paradox — one targeting statements implying necessities, the other targeting statements implying possibilities. By treating a thought experiment as a stylized paradox, the idea that it re…Read more
  •  3
    Uncaused decisions and pre-decisional blindspots
    Philosophical Studies 45 (1). 1984.
  • The Evolution of Thought Experiment
    In Thought experiments, Oxford University Press. 1992.
    This chapter seeks to define “thought experiment” and dig to its origin. It argues that thought experiments evolved from experiment through a process of attenuation. This builds inductive momentum behind the theme that thought experiments are experiments.
  •  9
    The ethics of empty worlds
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83 (3): 349-356. 2005.
    Drawing inspiration from the ethical pluralism of G. E. Moore's Principia Ethica, I contend that one empty world can be morally better than another. By ?empty? I mean that it is devoid of concrete entities (things that have a position in space or time). These worlds have no thickets or thimbles, no thinkers, no thoughts. Infinitely many of these worlds have laws of nature, abstract entities, and perhaps, space and time. These non-concrete differences are enough to make some of them better than o…Read more
  •  39
    The bottle imp and the prediction paradox, II
    Philosophia 17 (3): 351-354. 1987.
  •  2
    The bottle imp and the prediction paradox
    Philosophia 15 (4): 421-424. 1986.
  • Scepticism About Thought Experiments
    In Thought experiments, Oxford University Press. 1992.
    This chapter presents and motivates the issues surrounding thought experiments by assembling the case against their use. It begins by exploring the more specific charge that thought experiment is just introspection, then concentrates on the charge that it is merely an atavistic appeal to ordinary language. Even if thought experiment is distinct from either of these methods, it strongly resembles them. Hence, details of both introspection and the appeal to ordinary language will be discussed in t…Read more
  •  7
    Self-strengthening empathy
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (1): 75-98. 1998.
    Stepping into the other guy's shoes works best when you resemble him. After all, the procedure is to use yourself as a model: in goes hypothetical beliefs and desires, out comes hypothetical actions and revised beliefs and desires. If you are structurally analogous to the empathee, then accurate inputs generate accurate outputs-just as with any other simulation. The greater the degree of isomorphism, the more dependable and precise the results. This sensitivity to degrees of resemblance suggests…Read more
  •  14
    Self-Strengthening Empathy
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (1): 75-98. 1998.
    Stepping into the other guy’s shoes works best when you resemble him. After all, the procedure is to use yourself as a model: in goes hypothetical beliefs and desires, out comes hypothetical actions and revised beliefs and desires. If you are structurally analogous to the empathee, then accurate inputs generate accurate outputs---just as with any other simulation. The greater the degree of isomorphism, the more dependable and precise the results. This sensitivity to degrees of resemblance sugges…Read more
  •  28
    Rationality as an Absolute Concept
    Philosophy 66 (258): 473-486. 1991.
    My thesis is that ‘rational’ is an absolute concept like ‘flat’ and ‘clean’. Absolute concepts are best defined as absences. In the case of flatness, the absence of bumps, curves, and irregularities. In the case of cleanliness, the absence of dirt. Rationality, then, is the absence of irrationalities such as bias, circularity, dogmatism, and inconsistency.
  • Mach and Inner Cognitive Africa
    In Thought experiments, Oxford University Press. 1992.
    This chapter focuses on the views of Australian philosopher-physicist Ernst Mach, the earliest and most systematic writer on thought experiments. It discusses Mach's response to the problem of informativeness. It then details the book's disagreements with Mach. It is argued that Mach's mistakes can be traced to his sensationalism and a one-sided diet of examples. His sensationalism led him to overemphasize the mentalistic aspects of thought experiment and to throw away tools needed to explain it…Read more
  • Our Most Curious Device
    In Thought experiments, Oxford University Press. 1992.
    This chapter illustrates the power of thought experiments by assembling influential thought experiments from the history of science. It lays out the book's plan to understand philosophical thought experiments by concentrating on their resemblance to scientific relatives. Points of difference between philosophical and scientific thought experiments give a preview of obstacles that must be overcome in the course of the campaign. Naive and sophisticated reservations about the philosophical cases ar…Read more
  •  53
    Newcomb's problem: Recalculations for the one-boxer
    Theory and Decision 15 (4): 399-404. 1983.
  •  100
    Is Epistemic Preferability Transitive?
    Analysis 41 (3). 1980.
  • Introduction
    In Thought experiments, Oxford University Press. 1992.
    This introductory chapter begins with a brief description of the purpose of this book, which is to present a general theory of thought experiments. The discussion includes thought experiments from many disparate fields, ranging from aesthetics to zoology. The primary goal is to establish true and interesting generalizations about them. Success here will radiate to the secondary goal of understanding philosophical thought experiments. An overview of the subsequent chapters is presented.
  • Kuhntradictions
    In Thought experiments, Oxford University Press. 1992.
    This chapter focuses on Thomas Kuhn's account of thought experiments. It begins with what Kuhn takes to be the smart talk about thought experiments. It then details Kuhn's amendments to this view and raises objections, most of which are directed against the notion of local incoherence. Finally, Kuhn's error is reconstructed in order to salvage the considerable insight that it contains.
  •  1
    Hearing silence: The perception and introspection of absences
    In Matthew Nudds & Casey O'Callaghan (eds.), Sounds and Perception, Oxford University Press. 2009.
    in Sounds and Perception: New Philosophical Essays, ed. by Matthew Nudds and Casey O’Callaghan (Oxford University Press, forthcoming in 2008)
  •  30
    Epistemic and classical validity
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 11 (4). 1982.
  • Fallacies and Antifallacies
    In Thought experiments, Oxford University Press. 1992.
    This chapter examines the hazards and pseudohazards of thought experiment. It attacks most skepticism about thought experiment as arbitrary. It argues that once the standards that are customary for compasses, stethoscopes, and other testing devices are applied, thought experiments measure up. They should be used as part of a diversified portfolio of techniques. Although all these devices are individually susceptible to abuse, fallacy, and error, they provide a network of cross-checks that make f…Read more
  •  2
    Debunkers and assurers
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69 (4). 1991.
    This Article does not have an abstract