• Quinov otáznik
    Ostium 3 (2). 2007.
  •  3
    Ockham a insolunilia 1
    Ostium 2 (4). 2006.
  •  35
    Stealing Harman’s Thought: knowledge saboteurs and dogmatists
    Synthese 198 (Suppl 7): 1787-1799. 2018.
    You receive a pink packet from Miss Lead, a notoriously deceptive truth-teller. You know that if you open the packet and do not find blank pages, then you will justifiably change your mind about the evidence being misleading. Indeed, you will infer that your previous fears about misleading evidence were themselves founded on misleading evidence. Should you open the pink packet? No, answers an advocate of self-censorship. Yes, answers an advocate of the principle that you should base conclusions …Read more
  •  31
    Other‐Centric Reasoning
    Metaphilosophy 49 (4): 489-509. 2018.
    This article considers question‐begging's opposite fallacy. Instead of relying on my beliefs for my premises when I should be using my adversary's beliefs, I rely on my adversary's beliefs when I should rely on my own. Just as question‐begging emerges from egocentrism, its opposite emerges from other‐centrism. Stepping into the other person's shoes is an effective strategy for understanding him. But you must return to your own shoes when forming your beliefs. Evidence is agent centered. Other‐ce…Read more
  •  144
    Was Descartes's cogito a diagonal deduction?
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 37 (3): 346-351. 1986.
    Peter Slezak and William Boos have independently advanced a novel interpretation of Descartes's "cogito". The interpretation portrays the "cogito" as a diagonal deduction and emphasizes its resemblance to Godel's theorem and the Liar. I object that this approach is flawed by the fact that it assigns 'Buridan sentences' a legitimate role in Descartes's philosophy. The paradoxical nature of these sentences would have the peculiar result of undermining Descartes's "cogito" while enabling him to "di…Read more
  •  35
    Uncaused decisions and pre-decisional blindspots
    Philosophical Studies 45 (1). 1984.
  •  106
    The ethics of empty worlds
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 83 (3): 349-356. 2005.
    Drawing inspiration from the ethical pluralism of G. E. Moore's Principia Ethica, I contend that one empty world can be morally better than another. By ?empty? I mean that it is devoid of concrete entities (things that have a position in space or time). These worlds have no thickets or thimbles, no thinkers, no thoughts. Infinitely many of these worlds have laws of nature, abstract entities, and perhaps, space and time. These non-concrete differences are enough to make some of them better than o…Read more
  •  39
    The bottle imp and the prediction paradox, II
    Philosophia 17 (3): 351-354. 1987.
  •  40
    The bottle imp and the prediction paradox
    Philosophia 15 (4): 421-424. 1986.
  •  44
    Self-strengthening empathy
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (1): 75-98. 1998.
    Stepping into the other guy's shoes works best when you resemble him. After all, the procedure is to use yourself as a model: in goes hypothetical beliefs and desires, out comes hypothetical actions and revised beliefs and desires. If you are structurally analogous to the empathee, then accurate inputs generate accurate outputs-just as with any other simulation. The greater the degree of isomorphism, the more dependable and precise the results. This sensitivity to degrees of resemblance suggests…Read more
  •  11
    Self-Strengthening Empathy
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (1): 75-98. 1998.
    Stepping into the other guy’s shoes works best when you resemble him. After all, the procedure is to use yourself as a model: in goes hypothetical beliefs and desires, out comes hypothetical actions and revised beliefs and desires. If you are structurally analogous to the empathee, then accurate inputs generate accurate outputs---just as with any other simulation. The greater the degree of isomorphism, the more dependable and precise the results. This sensitivity to degrees of resemblance sugges…Read more
  •  23
    Rationality as an Absolute Concept
    Philosophy 66 (258): 473-486. 1991.
    My thesis is that ‘rational’ is an absolute concept like ‘flat’ and ‘clean’. Absolute concepts are best defined as absences. In the case of flatness, the absence of bumps, curves, and irregularities. In the case of cleanliness, the absence of dirt. Rationality, then, is the absence of irrationalities such as bias, circularity, dogmatism, and inconsistency.
  •  52
    Newcomb's problem: Recalculations for the one-boxer
    Theory and Decision 15 (4): 399-404. 1983.
  •  16
    Hearing silence: The perception and introspection of absences
    In Matthew Nudds & Casey O'Callaghan (eds.), Sounds and Perception, Oxford University Press. 2009.
    in Sounds and Perception: New Philosophical Essays, ed. by Matthew Nudds and Casey O’Callaghan (Oxford University Press, forthcoming in 2008)
  •  99
    Is Epistemic Preferability Transitive?
    Analysis 41 (3). 1980.
  •  30
    Epistemic and classical validity
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 11 (4). 1982.
  •  10
    Debunkers and assurers
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 69 (4). 1991.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  33
    Commentary
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 33 (Supplement): 161-170. 1995.
  •  63
    Time Travel, Parahistory and Hume
    Philosophy 62 (240). 1987.
    THE PURPOSE OF THIS ARTICLE IS TO SHOW HOW HUME’S SCEPTICISM ABOUT MIRACLES GENERATES "EPISTEMOLOGICAL" SCEPTICISM ABOUT TIME TRAVEL. SO THE PRIMARY QUESTION RAISED HERE IS "CAN ONE KNOW THAT TIME TRAVEL HAS OCCURED?" RATHER THAN "CAN TIME TRAVEL OCCUR?" I ARGUE THAT ATTEMPTS TO SHOW THE EXISTENCE OF TIME TRAVEL WOULD FACE THE SAME METHODOLOGICAL PROBLEMS AS THE ONES CONFRONTING ATTEMPTS TO DEMONSTRATE THE EXISTENCE OF PARANORMAL EVENTS. SINCE HUMEAN SCEPTICISM EXTENDS TO THE STUDY OF PARANORMAL…Read more
  •  18
    Ducking Harm
    with Christopher Boorse
    Journal of Philosophy 85 (3): 115-134. 1988.
  •  314
    Ducking harm
    Journal of Philosophy 85 (3): 115-134. 1988.
  •  6
    Do not pass by my epitaph, Wayfarer, but when you have stopped, hear and learn, then depart. There is no boat, To carry you to Hades, No ferryman Charon, No judge Aeacus, No Dog Cerberus. All of us below have become bones and ashes. Truly, I have nothing more to tell you. So depart, wayfarer, Lest dead though I am I seem to you to be a teller of vain tales.
  •  52
    When my son Maxwell was a toddler, he did not believe he was ever an infant. This skepticism became manifest when he started identifying himself in photographs. Maxwell was accurate with photographs that were taken after age six months. But he dismissed earlier pictures as photographs of "BABIES".
  •  13
    Review: A Reply to Critics (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (3). 2005.
  •  89
    The vanishing point is a representational gap that organizes the visual field. Study of this singularity revolutionized art in the fifteenth century. Further reflection on the vanishing point invites the conjecture that the self is an absence. This paper opens with perceptual peculiarities of the vanishing point and closes with the metaphysics of personal identity
  •  55
    Seizing the opportunity to apply what they had learned, the students declared a cheating competition. Outspoken participants (future lawyers, politicians, and captains of industry) bragged about their ruses. But to their chagrin, an ethics student prevailed.
  •  15
    Philoso
    with Abigail L. Rosenthal, Hallvard Lillehammer, Nml Nathan, William Lane Craig, and Christopher Miles Coope
    Philosophy 86 (2). 2011.
  •  18
    Contagious Blindspots: Formal Ignorance Spreads to Peers
    American Philosophical Quarterly 52 (4): 335-344. 2015.
    A blindspot is a consistent but inaccessible proposition. For instance, I cannot know 'The test is on Friday but I do not know it'. No contradiction follows from the supposition that you know my blindspot. But could you know my blindspot if we are epistemic peers? Epistemic peers have the same evidence and reasoning ability. So either both peers know a proposition or both are ignorant. Since I cannot know my blindspot, neither can my peer. Thus the formal ignorance associated with blindspots spr…Read more