•  157
    Yablo's paradox and Kindred infinite liars
    Mind 107 (425): 137-155. 1998.
    This is a defense and extension of Stephen Yablo's claim that self-reference is completely inessential to the liar paradox. An infinite sequence of sentences of the form 'None of these subsequent sentences are true' generates the same instability in assigning truth values. I argue Yablo's technique of substituting infinity for self-reference applies to all so-called 'self-referential' paradoxes. A representative sample is provided which includes counterparts of the preface paradox, Pseudo-Scotus…Read more
  •  88
    Recalcitrant variations of the prediction paradox
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60 (4). 1982.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  52
    Problems with electoral evaluations of expert opinions
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 35 (1): 47-53. 1984.
    An electoral evaluation of a set of expert opinions proceeds by treating the experts as voters. Although this method allows us to formalise our naive views about how to take expert advice, the formalisations are plagued by paradoxes which parallel those found in literature on social aggregation devices. This parallel suggests that our naive views about taking expert advice are in as much need of revision as our naive views about deriving group preferences from individual preferences. * I am inde…Read more
  •  70
    Logical luck
    Philosophical Quarterly 48 (192): 319-334. 1998.
  •  117
    Mirror notation: Symbol manipulation without inscription manipulation
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 28 (2): 141-164. 1999.
    Stereotypically, computation involves intrinsic changes to the medium of representation: writing new symbols, erasing old symbols, turning gears, flipping switches, sliding abacus beads. Perspectival computation leaves the original inscriptions untouched. The problem solver obtains the output by merely alters his orientation toward the input. There is no rewriting or copying of the input inscriptions; the output inscriptions are numerically identical to the input inscriptions. This suggests a lo…Read more
  •  30
    Did the intensity of my preferences double last night?
    Philosophy of Science 53 (2): 282-285. 1986.
    About twenty years ago, philosophers debated the verifiability of the statement “Last night everything doubled in size.” It seems that universal nocturnal expansion would double our rulers and tape measures making the size change indiscernible. I think that there is an internal analogue to the question “Did everything double in size last night?” The question “Did my preferences double in intensity last night?“ also raises problems of verification.
  •  100
    (1984). Conditional blindspots and the knowledge squeeze: A solution to the prediction paradox. Australasian Journal of Philosophy: Vol. 62, No. 2, pp. 126-135
  •  87
    A vague demonstration
    Linguistics and Philosophy 23 (5): 507-522. 2000.
    Poindexter points and asserts `That is Clinton''. But it is vague as to whether he pointed at Clinton or pointed at the more salient man, Gore. Since the vagueness only occurs at the level of reference fixing, the content of the identity proposition is precise. Indeed, it is either a necessary truth or a necessary falsehood. Since Poindexter''s utterance has a hidden truth value by virtue of vagueness, it increases the plausibility of epistemicism. Epistemicism says that vague statements have hi…Read more
  •  46
    A strengthened prediction paradox
    Philosophical Quarterly 36 (145): 504-513. 1986.
  •  240
    A thousand clones
    Mind 103 (409): 47-54. 1994.
  •  121
    We see in the dark
    Noûs 38 (3): 456-480. 2004.
    Do we need light to see? I argue that the black experience of a man in a perfectly dark cave is a representation of an absence of light, not an absence of representation. There is certainly a difference between his perceptual knowledge and that of his blind companion. Only the sighted man can tell whether the cave is dark just by looking. But perhaps he is merely inferring darkness from his failure to see. To get an unambiguous answer, I switch the focus from perceptual knowledge to non-epistemi…Read more
  •  151
    Consider the beginningless sequence: ... being less than 0.01 grams, being less than 0.1 grams, being less than 1 gram, being less than 10 grams ... There is no super-determinate in this chain. Just as the possibility of bottomless constitution shows that there may be no fundamental layer of reality with respect to objects , the possibility of bottomless determination shows that there may be no fundamental level of reality with respect to properties . This possibility supports Stephen Yablo's pr…Read more
  •  82
    Vague Music
    Philosophy 86 (2): 231-248. 2011.
    Is listening to music like looking through a kaleidoscope? Formalists contend that music is meaningless. Most music theorists concede that this austere thesis is surprisingly close to the truth. Nevertheless, they refute formalism with a little band of diffusely referential phenomena, such as musical quotation, onomatopoeia, exemplification, and leitmotifs. These curiosities ought to be pressed into a new campaign against assumptions that vagueness can only arise in the semantically lush setting…Read more
  •  74
    Logically Equivalent—But Closer to the Truth
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (2). 2007.
    Verisimilitude has the potential to deepen the understanding of mathematical progress, the principle of charity, and the psychology of regret. One obstacle is the widely held belief that two statements can vary in truthlikeness only if they vary in what they entail. This obstacle is removed with four types of counterexamples. The first concerns necessarily coextensive measurements that differ only with respect to their units (specifically length, area, and volume). The second class ofcounterexam…Read more
  •  129
    The art of the impossible
    In John Hawthorne & Tamar Szab'O. Gendler (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility, Oxford University Press. pp. 337--368. 2002.
    Prize: One hundred dollars to the first person who identifies a picture of a logical impossibility. I may be willing to pay more for the painting itself. This finder’s fee is simply for pointing out the picture. Let me explain more precisely what I seek.
  •  27
    Semivaluationism: Putting Vagueness in Context in Context (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (2): 471-483. 2008.
  •  6
    The liar’s loophole
    The Philosophers' Magazine 50 106-107. 2010.
  •  9
    Sorensen's Reply to Bunzl and Feldman
    Informal Logic 17 (3). 1995.
  •  43
    Smartfounding is the opposite of “dumbfounding” introduced by Jonathan Haidt’s research on disgust. Dumbfounders have general competence at thought experiment. However, they are flustered by thought experiments that support repugnant conclusions. Instead of following the supposition wherever it leads, they avoid unsettling implications by adding extraneous information or ignoring stipulated conditions. The dumbfounded commit performance errors, often seeming to regress to the answers of people w…Read more
  •  441
    Bald-faced lies! Lying without the intent to deceive
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 88 (2): 251-264. 2007.
    Surprisingly, the fact that the speaker is lying is sometimes common knowledge between everyone involved. Strangely, we condemn these bald-faced lies more severely than disguised lies. The wrongness of lying springs from the intent to deceive – just the feature missing in the case of bald-faced lies. These puzzling lies arise systematically when assertions are forced. Intellectual duress helps to explain another type of non-deceptive false assertion : lying to yourself. In the end, I conclude th…Read more
  •  70
    Paradoxes of Rationality
    In Alfred R. Mele & Piers Rawling (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Rationality, Oup Usa. 2004.
    Sorensen provides a panoramic view of paradoxes of theoretical and practical rationality. These puzzles are organized as apparent counterexamples to attractive principles such as the principle of charity, the transitivity of preferences, and the principle that we should maximize expected utility. The following paradoxes are discussed: fearing fictions, the surprise test paradox, Pascal’s Wager, Pollock’s Ever Better wine, Newcomb’s problem, the iterated prisoner’s dilemma, Kavka’s paradoxes of d…Read more
  •  96
    Empty quotation
    Analysis 68 (1): 57-61. 2008.
  •  60
    A séance with an immortal
    Philosophy 81 (3): 395-416. 2006.
    To understand death, you need to compare mortality with immortality. I am here to help. In addition to my personal testimony, I present highlights from a survey of immortal species and a survey of infinitistic varieties of mortality. These field studies rebut Fredrich Nietzsche’s thesis that immortality is inevitably repetitious, Bernard Williams’ allegation that immortality is inevitably boring, and Epicurus’ thesis that death cannot be bad for you. On the positive side, the study shows that th…Read more
  •  7
    Direct Reference and Vague Identity
    Philosophical Topics 28 (1): 177-194. 2000.