•  7
    Direct Reference and Vague Identity
    Philosophical Topics 28 (1): 177-194. 2000.
  •  1
    Blindspots
    Mind 99 (393): 137-140. 1990.
  •  56
    Moore's problem with iterated belief
    Philosophical Quarterly 50 (198): 28-43. 2000.
    Positive thinkers love Watty Piper's The little engine that could. The story features a train laden with toys for deserving children on the other side of the mountain. After the locomotive breaks down, a sequence of snooty locomotives come up the track. Each engine refuses to pull the train up the mountain. They are followed by a weary old locomotive that declines, saying "I cannot. I cannot. I cannot." But then a bright blue engine comes up the track. He manages to chug over the mountain by ave…Read more
  •  53
    A Reply to Critics (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (3): 712-728. 2007.
  •  71
    Ambiguity, Discretion, and the Sorites
    The Monist 81 (2): 215-232. 1998.
    Sooner or later, every paradox is accused of equivocation. Usually sooner. For equivocation is a simple, well understood fallacy. People first try to explain a mystery in terms of what is familiar. If postulating a simple ambiguity fails, more subtle ambiguities will be postulated. Those who persist with this diagnosis elaborate the charge of equivocation into an esoteric form.
  •  111
    Can God create a stone too heavy for him to lift? Can time have a beginning? Which came first, the chicken or the egg? Riddles, paradoxes, conundrums--for millennia the human mind has found such knotty logical problems both perplexing and irresistible. Now Roy Sorensen offers the first narrative history of paradoxes, a fascinating and eye-opening account that extends from the ancient Greeks, through the Middle Ages, the Enlightenment, and into the twentieth century. When Augustine asked what God…Read more
  •  49
    Zande Sorites
    Erkenntnis (S7): 1-14. 2013.
    When Bertrand Russell alerted Gottlob Frege to an inconsistency in his Grundgesetze, Frege relinquished deep commitments. When Edward Evans-Pritchard alerted the Azande to an inconsistency in their beliefs about witchcraft inheritance, they did not revise their beliefs. Nor did they engage in the defensive maneuvers depicted in Plato’s dialogues. Evans-Pritchard characterized their indifference to contradiction as irrational. My historical thesis is that the ensuing anthropological debate mirror…Read more
  •  1
    The vanishing point is a representational gap that organizes the visual field. Study of this singularity revolutionized art in the fifteenth century. Further reflection on the vanishing point invites the conjecture that the self is an absence. This paper opens with perceptual peculiarities of the vanishing point and closes with the metaphysics of personal identity
  •  152
    Vagueness and contradiction
    Oxford University Press. 2001.
    Roy Sorenson offers a unique exploration of an ancient problem: vagueness. Did Buddha become a fat man in one second? Is there a tallest short giraffe? According to Sorenson's epistemicist approach, the answers are yes! Although vagueness abounds in the way the world is divided, Sorenson argues that the divisions are sharp; yet we often do not know where they are. Written in Sorenson'e usual inventive and amusing style, this book offers original insight on language and logic, the way world is, a…Read more
  •  36
    Vagueness and Contradiction
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (3): 695-703. 2005.
  •  129
    Vagueness has no function in law
    Legal Thoery 7 (4): 385--415. 2001.
    Islamic building codes require mosques to face Mecca. The further Islam spreads, the more apt are believers to fall into a quandary. X faces Y only when the front of X is closer to Y than any other side of X. So the front of the mosque should be oriented along a shortest path to Mecca. Which way is that? Does the path to Mecca tunnel through the earth? Or does the path follow the surface of the earth?
  •  95
    Unicorn Atheism
    Noûs 52 (2): 373-388. 2018.
    Kripshe treats ‘god’ as an empty natural kind term such as ‘unicorn’. She applies Saul Kripke's fresh views about empty natural kinds to ‘god’. Metaphysically, says Kripshe, there are no possible worlds in which there are gods. Gods could not have existed, given that they do not actually exist and never did. Epistemologically, godlessness is an a posteriori discovery. Kripshe dismisses the gods in the same breath that she dismisses mermaids. Semantically, the perspective Kripshe finds most persp…Read more
  •  47
    The Vanishing Point
    The Monist 90 (3): 432-456. 2007.
  •  148
    The sorites and the Generic Overgeneralization Effect
    Analysis 72 (3): 444-449. 2012.
    Sorites arguments employ an induction step such as ‘Small numbers have small successors’. People deduce that there must be an exception to the generalization but are reluctant to conclude that the generalization is false. My hypothesis is that the reluctance is due to the "Generic Overgeneralization Effect". Although the propounder of the sorites paradox intends the induction step to be a universal generalization, hearers assimilate universal generalizations to generic generalizations (for insta…Read more
  •  144
    The Twin Towers riddle
    Philosophical Studies 162 (1): 109-117. 2013.
  •  65
    Two fields of vision
    Philosophical Issues 21 (1): 456-473. 2011.
  •  67
    The liar’s loophole
    The Philosophers' Magazine 50 (50): 106-107. 2010.
  •  85
    The metaphysics of words
    Philosophical Studies 81 (2-3). 1996.
    Semantic indeterminacy is the ether of philosophy of language. It fills the interstices of our intentions and pervades accounts of presupposition, tense, fiction, translation, and especially, vagueness. Yet semantic indeterminacy is as impossible as ectoplasm. Indeed, more so! The demonstration need only borrow a few assumptions used elsewhere in widely accepted impossibility results. Since an impossibility is never a necessary condition for anything actual, semantic indeterminacy must be superf…Read more
  •  46
    This report is also a consolidated response to three memoranda. The legal division requested an historical review as patent support. Engineering has solicited input on product development. Thirdly, I am responding to a plea from the Personnel Department. Their headhunters have asked for more specific advice on how to recruit skeptics.
  •  91
    The aesthetics of mirror reversal
    Philosophical Studies 100 (2): 175-191. 2000.
    A flop is a picture that mirror reverses the original scene. Some flops are reversed copies. For instance, mirror reversal is systematic with technologies that require contact between a template and an imprint surface. Other flops are just pictures that have undergone the operation of flopping. For example, a slide that is inserted backwards into a projector is a flop.
  •  73
    Semivaluationism: Putting vagueness in context in context
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (2). 2008.
  •  291
    Seeing dark things: the philosophy of shadows
    Oxford University Press. 2008.
    The eclipse riddle -- Seeing surfaces -- The disappearing act -- Spinning shadows -- Berkeley's shadow -- Para-reflections -- Para-refractions : shadowgrams and the black drop -- Goethe's colored shadows -- Filtows -- Holes in the light -- Black and blue -- Seeing in black and white -- We see in the dark -- Hearing silence.
  •  111
    Sharp Edges from Hedges: Fatalism, Vagueness and Epistemic Possibility
    Philosophical Studies 131 (3): 607-626. 2006.
    Mights plug gaps. If p lacks a truth-value, then ‘It might be that p’ should also lack truth-value. Yet epistemic hedges often turn an unassertible statement into an assertible one. The phenomenon is illustrated in detail for two kinds of statements that are frequently alleged to be counterexamples to the principle of bivalence: future contingents and statements that apply predicates to borderline cases. The paper concludes by exploring the prospects for generalizing this gap-plugging strategy.
  •  146
    Seeing Intersecting Eclipses
    Journal of Philosophy 96 (1): 25. 1999.
  •  74
    Silhouettes: A Reply from the Dark Side (review)
    Acta Analytica 26 (2): 199-211. 2011.
    This is a reply to Casey O'Callaghan and Jonathan Westphal’s comments on Seeing Dark Things: The Philosophy of Shadows. Both attempt to soften the blow to intuition that comes from the most controversial thesis of the book: we see the backs of back-lit objects. Each characterizes the viewing of silhouettes as a kind of marginal seeing that only discloses shapes, sizes and location. In response, photographs are presented to show that silhouettes are typically three-dimensional and they often have…Read more
  •  41
    Imagine a child playing in the afternoon sun, suddenly jerking her arm one way then the other, trying to catch her shadow out. The game, the child soon learns, is one that she can never win. Her shadow moves the moment she does. Such childish games father common sense wisdom; when things move, so do their shadows. Or do they? A spinning sphere casts a shadow. But does its shadow also spin? The question takes you by surprise. Surely not? you think. But then again, why not? This is the trope of So…Read more
  •  34
    Précis of Vagueness and Contradiction
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (3): 678-685. 2007.
  •  64
    Précis of vagueness and contradiction (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (3). 2005.
    Rorty goes on to connect the sorites paradox to analytic philosophy’s long standing concern with the correspondence theory of truth. How do our words hook up with reality? Do our categories map pre-existing contours? The nominalist answers that “facts” are just projections of our forms of speech. Rorty characterizes epistemicism as a hyper-realist backlash. In addition to thinking that our scientific terminology cuts nature at the joint, the epistemicist asserts that even the vague vocabulary of…Read more