•  258
    Numbers, minds, and bodies: A fresh look at mind-body dualism
    Philosophical Perspectives 12 349-371. 1998.
    In this essay, we explore a fresh avenue into mind-body dualism by considering a seemingly distant question posed by Frege: "Why is it absurd to suppose that Julius Caesar is a number?". The essay falls into three main parts. In the first, through an exploration of Frege’s Julius Caesar problem, we attempt to expose two maxims applicable to the mind-body problem. In the second part, we draw on those maxims in arguing that “full blown dualism” is preferable to more modest, property-theoretic, ver…Read more
  •  1194
    Minimalism and truth
    Noûs 31 (2): 170-196. 1997.
    This paper canvasses the various dimensions along which theories of truth may disagree about the extent to which truth is minimal.
  •  78
    Framing the thisness issue
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 75 (1). 1997.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  75
    Dennett’s Logical Behaviorism
    Philosophical Topics 22 (1-2): 189-258. 1994.
  •  141
    Compatibilist semantics in metaphysics: A case study
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (1). 1996.
    (1996). Compatibilist semantics in metaphysics: A case study. Australasian Journal of Philosophy: Vol. 74, No. 1, pp. 117-134. doi: 10.1080/00048409612347101.
  •  219
    A world of universals
    Philosophical Studies 91 (3): 205-219. 1998.
  •  39
    The need to address our question arises from two sources, one in Kant and the other in a certain type of response to so-called Reformed epistemology. The first source consists in a tendency to distinguish theoretical beliefs from practical beliefs , and to treat theistic belief as mere practical belief. We trace this tendency in Kant's corpus, and compare and contrast it with Aquinas's view and a more conservative Kantian view. We reject the theistic-belief-as-mere-practical-belief view: it is b…Read more
  •  93
    Dennett’s Logical Behaviorism
    with Brian P. McLaughlin
    Philosophical Topics 22 (1-2): 189-258. 1994.
  •  2
    Reply to Cohen
    Philosophical Issues 10 (1): 117-120. 2000.
  •  94
    Evidence, experience and decision
    Philosophical Studies 180 (8): 2491-2502. 2023.
  •  20
    Deeply Contingent A Priori Knowledge
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2): 247-269. 2002.
    The argument is not, however, problem-free. First: while the meaning of s might not guarantee a verifying state of affairs, mightn’t the fact of one’s believing that s is true guarantee a verifying state of affairs? And mightn’t this fact be exploited to secure knowledge of truths that are deeply contingent? Second: the argument seems to rely on the principle that if I can conceive that not P is actually the case, then I do not know that P. But it is generally agreed that a knowledge-conferring …Read more
  •  62
    Disjunctivism
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 80 (1): 145-216. 2006.
    [John Hawthorne] We examine some well-known disjunctivist projects in the philosophy of perception, mainly in a critical vein. Our discussion is divided into four parts. Following some introductory remarks, we examine in part two the link between object-dependent contents and disjunctivism. In part three, we explore the disjunctivist's use of discriminability facts as a basis for understanding experience. In part four, we examine an interesting argument for disjunctivism that has been offered by…Read more
  •  115
    Are Beliefs about God Theoretical Beliefs? Reflections on Aquinas and Kant
    with Daniel Howard-Snyder
    Religious Studies 32 (2). 1996.
    The need to address our question arises from two sources, one in Kant and the other in a certain type of response to so-called Reformed epistemology. The first source consists in a tendency to distinguish theoretical beliefs from practical beliefs (commitments to the world's being a certain way versus commitments to certain pictures to live by), and to treat theistic belief as mere practical belief. We trace this tendency in Kant's corpus, and compare and contrast it with Aquinas's view and a mo…Read more
  •  30
    Reply to Cohen
    Noûs 34 (s1). 2000.
  •  491
    Against Conservatism in Metaphysics
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 82 45-75. 2018.
    In his recent book, Daniel Korman contrasts ontological conservatives with permissivists and eliminativists about ontology. Roughly speaking, conservatives admit the existence of ‘ordinary objects' like trees, dogs, and snowballs, but deny the existence of ‘extraordinary objects', like composites of trees and dogs. Eliminativists, on the other hand, deny many or all ordinary objects, while permissivists accept both ordinary and extraordinary objects. Our aim in this paper is to outline some of o…Read more
  •  44
    Scotus on Universals
    Oxford Studies in Medieval Philosophy 4 (1). 2016.
    Scotus contended that the humanity of Socrates has less than a numerical unity. But what does that claim come to? And how does Scotus’s position relate to familiar debates concerning the existence of universals and/or tropes? This paper provides a detailed sketch of Scotus’s view, arguing that it is not intrinsic to Socrates’s nature that it has numerical unity. The paper goes on to explain why Ockham’s attack on the coherence of Scotus’s argument does not succeed. What initially looks like a su…Read more
  •  73
    Statistical evidence and incentives in the law
    Philosophical Issues 31 (1): 128-145. 2021.
    Philosophical Issues, Volume 31, Issue 1, Page 128-145, October 2021.
  •  6
    Seeing and Demonstration
    with Mark Scala
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (1): 199-206. 2000.
    We see things. We also perceptually demonstrate things. There seems to be some sort of link between these two phenomena. Indeed. in the standard case, the former is accompanied by a capacity for the latter. One sees a dog and can, on the basis of one’s perceptual capacities, think thoughts of the form ‘That is F’. But how strong is that link? Does seeing a thing (in the success sense of seeing) inevitably bring with it the capacity for perceptually demonstrating it? In what follows, we argue for…Read more
  •  108
    Moral Vagueness and Epistemicism
    Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 23 (2). 2022.
    Epistemicism is one of the main approaches to the phenomenon of vagueness. But how does it fare in its treatment of_ moral_ vagueness? This paper has two goals. First, I shall explain why various recent arguments against an epistemicist approach to moral vagueness are unsuccessful. Second, I shall explain how, in my view, reflection on the Sorites can inform normative ethics in powerful and interesting ways. In this connection, I shall be putting the epistemicist treatment to work, engaging with…Read more
  •  53
    Knowledge and Lotteries
    Philosophical Quarterly 55 (219): 353-356. 2005.
  •  16
    Intrinsic Properties and Natural Relations
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (2): 399-403. 2001.
    Assuming that we find the concept of naturalness coherent, we shall no doubt wish to allow that certain relations count as highly natural. Many of us will think that various spatio-temporal and causal relations—is the cause of, is spatially separated from, is later than—are highly natural. Some of us will think that various basic semantic and mentalistic relations—refers to, attends to, believes.…--- are highly natural. Some will think that various logico-mathematical relations—being the success…Read more
  •  29
    Belief and Behavior
    Mind and Language 8 (4): 461-486. 1993.
  •  13
    The methodology of political theory
    In Herman Cappelen, Tamar Gendler & John P. Hawthorne (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophical Methodology, Oxford University Press. 2016.
    This article examines the methodology of a core branch of contemporary political theory or philosophy: “analytic” political theory. After distinguishing political theory from related fields, such as political science, moral philosophy, and legal theory, the article discusses the analysis of political concepts. It then turns to the notions of principles and theories, as distinct from concepts, and reviews the methods of assessing such principles and theories (e.g., the reflective-equilibrium meth…Read more
  •  79
    This study addresses a range of central topics in Anglo-American philosophy of language.
  •  29
    Reply to Speaks
    Philosophical Studies 178 (9): 3061-3065. 2020.
  •  112
    The Necessity of Mathematics
    Noûs 54 (3): 549-577. 2020.
    Some have argued for a division of epistemic labor in which mathematicians supply truths and philosophers supply their necessity. We argue that this is wrong: mathematics is committed to its own necessity. Counterfactuals play a starring role.
  •  1121
    Operator arguments revisited
    Philosophical Studies 176 (11): 2933-2959. 2019.
    Certain passages in Kaplan’s ‘Demonstratives’ are often taken to show that non-vacuous sentential operators associated with a certain parameter of sentential truth require a corresponding relativism concerning assertoric contents: namely, their truth values also must vary with that parameter. Thus, for example, the non-vacuity of a temporal sentential operator ‘always’ would require some of its operands to have contents that have different truth values at different times. While making no claims …Read more
  •  29
    Précis of narrow content
    Philosophical Studies 178 (9): 3013-3016. 2020.