• Competing Pictures
    In Ethics without principles, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    Argues against views alternative to particularism in detail, including the views of McNaughton and Rawling, Crisp, Raz, Scanlon, Hooker, Parfit, and also appeals to Aristotelian philosophy of science.
  • Contributory Reasons
    In Ethics without principles, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    Considers the nature of contributory reasons, contrasting the contributory with the overall. Also considers attempts to characterise the nature of the contributory in terms of overall oughts, arguing that all such attempts fail. Also considers arguments that there can be oughts without reasons, and rejects these too. Concludes that reasons are best understood in terms of the relation of favouring.
  •  10
    Book review of 'Aspects of reason' by P. Grice.
  • Consequential Matters
    In Practical Reality, Oxford University Press. 2000.
    Argues against disjunctive accounts of action‐explanation. Also considers the metaphysics of reasons and returns to the distinction between internalism and externalism in the theory of normative reasons. Ends by asking how objective our account of reasons should be.
  •  28
    Contemplating one's nagel1
    Philosophical Books 29 (1): 1-16. 1988.
  • Can Holism be True?
    In Ethics without principles, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    Considers various attempts to show that holism in the theory of reasons must be false. Distinguishes various forms of atomism, considers various appeals to notions of complete reasons and full explanations, asks whether moral reasoning is a form of inference and whether conceptual competence requires the existence of natural patterns, and ends by asking whether a particularist can allow that some moral considerations have a default relevance.
  • Review of Paul Grice: The Conception of Value (review)
    Ethics 104 (1): 161-163. 1993.
  •  8
    Book revies
    Mind 91 (364): 618-621. 1982.
  • Beyond Favouring
    In Ethics without principles, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    Suggests ways of characterising the favouring relation by contrasting it with other forms of relevance, such as enabling and intensifying. Offers examples of the distinction between favouring and enabling in the theory of explanation and in epistemology.
  •  67
    Berkeley, an introduction
    Blackwell. 1987.
    This new introduction to the main themes of Berkeley′s philosophy assumes no previous knowlege of philosophy and will be accessible to first-year students and to the interested general reader. It also offers and defends its own interpretation of Berkeley′ position. Jonathan Dancy argues that we understand Berkeley′s idealism best if we take seriously his claim that realism (the view that material things have an existence independent of the mind) derives from a mistaken use of abstraction. Stress…Read more
  •  262
    Berkeley's active self
    European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 1 (1): 5-20. 2005.
    The Author considers the strengths and weaknesses of Berkeley’s account of what he calls indifferently the soul, mind, spirit or self. Such an account deserves far more credit than he has standardly been awarded for a significantly modern position, most of which has mistakenly been credited to Schopenhauer. The Aauthor relates Berkeley’s views to those recently expressed by Bill Brewer and attempts to isolate the crucial difference between Berkeley and Schopenhauer.
  •  66
    Argues against G. E. Moore’s conception of organic unities, attempting to replace it with a conception more amenable to particularism. Considers the possibility of a form of default value acceptable to particularism. Ends by contrasting the views expressed here with those of Kagan.
  •  18
    A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 1998.
    This new edition of Berkeley's Principles of Human Knowledge has been designed especially for the student reader. It also includes the four letters between George Berkeley and Samuel Johnson, written in 1729-30. The text is supplemented by a comprehensive introduction, an analysis of the text, a glossary, detailed notes, and a full bibliography with guidance on further reading. Published alongside Berkeley's other masterpiece, the Three Dialogues this new edition aims to give the reader a thorou…Read more
  •  24
    Acting in the Light of the Appearances
    In Cynthia Macdonald & Graham Macdonald (eds.), McDowell and His Critics, Blackwell. 2006.
    This chapter contains section titled: I II III IV V VI VII.
  •  20
    Action in moral metaphysics
    In Constantine Sandis (ed.), New essays on the explanation of action, Palgrave-macmillan. pp. 398-417. 2009.
  •  763
    Introduction As its title indicates, this book is intended to provide an introduction to the main topics currently discussed under the rather unclear ...
  • As I Believe
    In Practical Reality, Oxford University Press. 2000.
    Considers and rejects the view that motivating reasons are best specified in psychological form rather than in non‐psychological form. Asks how we should then explain the fact that, if S acts for the reason that p, S must believe that p. It also asks whether the fact that the agent can be mistaken forces us to prefer the psychological form of explanation. It is argued that it does not, because explanation in terms of reasons is not factive; we explain S's action by appeal to what he believed eve…Read more
  •  214
    Acting in ignorance
    Frontiers of Philosophy in China 6 (3): 345-357. 2011.
    This paper considers and rejects the arguments that have been given in favour of the view that one can only act for the reason that p if one knows that p . The paper contrasts it with the view I hold, which is that one can act for the reason that p even if it is not the case that p
  • Acting for a Good Reason
    In Practical Reality, Oxford University Press. 2000.
    Argues that motivating reasons are not mental states of the agent but states of affairs. The main argument for this appeals to the normative realism established earlier. Since a reason to act is a state of affairs, the reasons in the light of which we act must also be capable of being states of affairs, for otherwise it would be impossible to act for a good reason. Our reasons are what we believe rather than that we so believe, or our so believing. I also consider and reject the view that our mo…Read more
  •  71
    A Companion to Epistemology (edited book)
    Wiley-Blackwell. 1992.
    Epistemology - the theory of knowledge and of justified belief - has always been of central importance in philosophy. Progress in other areas of philosophical research has often depended crucially on epistemological presuppositions. This Companion, with well over 250 articles ranging from summary discussions to major essays on topics of current controversy, is the first complete reference work devoted to the subject. All the main theoretical positions in epistemology are discussed and analysed, …Read more