•  373
    Death, badness, and the impossibility of experience
    The Journal of Ethics 1 (4): 341-353. 1997.
    Some have argued (following Epicurus) that death cannot be a bad thing for an individual who dies. They contend that nothing can be a bad for an individual unless the individual is able to experience it as bad. I argue against this Epicurean view, offering examples of things that an individual cannot experience as bad but are nevertheless bad for the individual. Further, I argue that death is relevantly similar.
  • Critical notices
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (4): 1083. 1999.
  •  43
    Causation and liability
    with Robert H. Ennis
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 15 (1): 33-40. 1986.
  •  7
    Critical Notice
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 31 (3): 427-444. 2001.
  • Contemporary Approaches to Free Will
    Dissertation, Cornell University. 1982.
    I begin with two compatibilist analyses of freedom: the conditional analysis and Lehrer's possible-worlds analysis. While certain arguments fail to undermine the conditional analysis, I present one which shows the inadequacy of the simple conditional analysis and a class of refinements of it. I find reason to reject the simple conditional analysis, refinements designed to account for "schizophrenic" objects, and Lehrer's conjunction of conditionals. ;I show how we might modify Lehrer's possible-…Read more
  •  18
    Critical Notice
    Religious Studies 28 (2). 1992.
  •  171
    Alternative possibilities: A reply to Lamb
    with Paul Hoffman
    Journal of Philosophy 91 (6): 321-326. 1994.
  •  7
    A New Compatibilism
    Philosophical Topics 24 (2): 49-66. 1996.
  •  33
    An Essay on Free Will
    Philosophical Review 97 (3): 401. 1988.
  •  503
    Abortion and Ownership
    The Journal of Ethics 17 (4): 275-304. 2013.
    I explore two thought-experiments in Judith Jarvis Thomson’s important article, “A Defense of Abortion”: the violinist example and the people-seeds example. I argue (contra Thomson) that you have a moral duty not to unplug yourself from the violinist and also a moral duty not to destroy a people-seed that has landed in your sofa. Nevertheless, I also argue that there are crucial differences between the thought-experiments and the contexts of pregnancy due to rape or to contraceptive failure. In …Read more
  •  96
    A new compatibilism
    Philosophical Topics 24 (2): 49-66. 1996.
  •  59
    Accommodating Counterfactual Attitudes: A Further Reply to Johansson
    with Anthony Brueckner
    The Journal of Ethics 18 (1): 19-21. 2014.
    Here we respond to Johansson’s main worry, as laid out in his, “Actual and Counterfactual Attitudes: Reply to Fischer and Brueckner.” We show how our principle BF*(dd*) can be adjusted to address this concern compatibly with our fundamental approach to responding to Lucretius
  •  181
    Abortion, autonomy, and control over one's body
    Social Philosophy and Policy 20 (2): 286-306. 2003.
    It is often thought that if a developing human being is considered a “person” from the beginning, then it would follow that abortion would be impermissible. For, after all, a person has a stringent right to life, and because life is a prerequisite for enjoying any other goods, it is plausible that the right to life is a “basic” or “fundamental” one, not easily overridden by other considerations. The right to life, it would seem, could not be outweighed by another individual's preferences, even p…Read more
  •  176
    The asymmetry of early death and late birth
    with Anthony Brueckner
    Philosophical Studies 71 (3): 327-331. 1993.
    In a previous paper, we argued that death's badness consists in the deprivation of pleasurable experiences which one would have had, had one died later rather than at the time of one's actual death. Thus, we argued that death can be a bad thing for the individual who dies, even if it is an experiential blank. But there is a pressing objection to this view, for if the view is correct, then it seems that it should also be the case that it is a bad thing for a person that he is born when he actuall…Read more
  •  426
    Why is death bad?
    with Anthony L. Brueckner
    Philosophical Studies 50 (2): 213-221. 1986.
    It seems that, whereas a person's death needn't be a bad thing for him, it can be. In some circumstances, death isn't a "bad thing" or an "evil" for a person. For instance, if a person has a terminal and very painful disease, he might rationally regard his own death as a good thing for him, or at least, he may regard it as something whose prospective occurrence shouldn't be regretted. But the attitude of a "normal" and healthy human being - adult or child - toward the prospect of his death is di…Read more
  •  97
    Being born earlier
    with Anthony Brueckner
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (1). 1998.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  27
    The Metaphysics of Free Will: An Essay on Control (review)
    Philosophical Review 106 (3): 450. 1997.
    The first, the Transfer Version, employs an inference principle concerning the transfer of one's powerlessness with respect to certain facts. The principle says, roughly, "If a person is powerless over one thing, and powerless over that thing's leading to another, then the person is powerless over the second thing". The key premises are the Fixity of the Past and the Fixity of the Laws. Fischer defends the transfer principle against objections that have been raised by Anthony Kenny and Michael S…Read more
  •  16
    Death's badness
    with Anthony L. Brueckner
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 74 (1): 37-45. 1993.