•  148
    Completeness results for some two-dimensional logics of actuality
    Review of Symbolic Logic 5 (2): 239-258. 2012.
    We provide a Hilbert-style axiomatization of the logic of , as well as a two-dimensional semantics with respect to which our logics are sound and complete. Our completeness results are quite general, pertaining to all such actuality logics that extend a normal and canonical modal basis. We also show that our logics have the strong finite model property and permit straightforward first-order extensions
  •  117
    Conditionals, probability, and nontriviality
    with Charles G. Morgan
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 24 (5): 455-467. 1995.
    We show that the implicational fragment of intuitionism is the weakest logic with a non-trivial probabilistic semantics which satisfies the thesis that the probabilities of conditionals are conditional probabilities. We also show that several logics between intuitionism and classical logic also admit non-trivial probability functions which satisfy that thesis. On the other hand, we also prove that very weak assumptions concerning negation added to the core probability conditions with the restric…Read more
  •  144
    In "Doing Well Enough: Toward a Logic for Common Sense Morality", Paul McNamara sets out a semantics for a deontic logic which contains the operator It is supererogatory that. As well as having a binary accessibility relation on worlds, that semantics contains a relative ordering relation, . For worlds u, v and w, we say that u w v when v is at least as good as u according to the standards of w. In this paper we axiomatize logics complete over three versions of the semantics. We call the stronge…Read more
  •  35
    Classically complete modal relevant logics
    Mathematical Logic Quarterly 39 (1): 165-177. 1993.
    A variety of modal logics based on the relevant logic R are presented. Models are given for each of these logics and completeness is shown. It is also shown that each of these logics admits Ackermann's rule γ and as a corollary of this it is proved that each logic is a conservative extension of its counterpart based on classical logic, hence we call them “classically complete”. MSC: 03B45, 03B46
  •  44
    Andersonian deontic logic
    Theoria 58 (1): 1-2. 1992.
  •  94
    An alternative semantics for quantified relevant logic
    with Robert Goldblatt
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 71 (1): 163-187. 2006.
    The quantified relevant logic RQ is given a new semantics in which a formula for all xA is true when there is some true proposition that implies all x-instantiations of A. Formulae are modelled as functions from variable-assignments to propositions, where a proposition is a set of worlds in a relevant model structure. A completeness proof is given for a basic quantificational system QR from which RQ is obtained by adding the axiom EC of 'extensional confinement': for all x(A V B) -> (A V for all…Read more
  •  51
    The Fact Semantics for Ramified Type Theory and the Axiom of Reducibility
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 48 (2): 237-251. 2007.
    This paper uses an atomistic ontology of universals, individuals, and facts to provide a semantics for ramified type theory. It is shown that with some natural constraints on the sort of universals and facts admitted into a model, the axiom of reducibility is made valid
  •  117
    Who's Afraid of Impossible Worlds?
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 38 (4): 516-526. 1997.
    A theory of ersatz impossible worlds is developed to deal with the problem of counterpossible conditionals. Using only tools standardly in the toolbox of possible worlds theorists, it is shown that we can construct a model for counterpossibles. This model is a natural extension of Lewis's semantics for counterfactuals, but instead of using classical logic as its base, it uses the logic LP
  •  49
    The admissibility of $\gamma$ in ${\rm R}4$
    with Robert K. Meyer
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 33 (2): 197-206. 1992.
  •  403
    A star-free semantics for R
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 60 (2). 1995.
    The purpose of this paper is to show that semantics for relevance logic, based on the Routley-Meyer semantics, can be given without using the Routley star operator to treat negation. In the resulting semantics, negation is treated implicationally. It is shown that, by the use of restrictions on the ternary accessibility relation, simplified by the use of some definitions, a semantics can be stipulated over which R is complete
  •  110
    Why we need a relevant theory of conditionals
    Topoi 13 (1): 31-36. 1994.
    This paper presents ConR (Conditional R), a logic of conditionals based on Anderson and Belnap''s system R. A Routley-Meyer-style semantics for ConR is given for the system (the completeness of ConR over this semantics is proved in E. Mares and A. Fuhrmann, A Relevant Theory of Conditionals (unpublished MS)). Moreover, it is argued that adopting a relevant theory of conditionals will improve certain theories that utilize conditionals, i.e. Lewis'' theory of causation, Lewis'' dyadic deontic logi…Read more
  •  116
    This paper provides an interpretation of the Routley-Meyer semantics for a weak negation-free relevant logic using Israel and Perry's theory of information. In particular, Routley and Meyer's ternary accessibility relation is given an interpretation in information-theoretic terms.
  •  78
    A paraconsistent theory of belief revision
    Erkenntnis 56 (2). 2002.
    This paper presents a theory of belief revision that allows people to come tobelieve in contradictions. The AGM theory of belief revision takes revision,in part, to be consistency maintenance. The present theory replacesconsistency with a weaker property called coherence. In addition to herbelief set, we take a set of statements that she rejects. These two sets arecoherent if they do not overlap. On this theory, belief revision maintains coherence.
  •  44
    The semantics ofr
    with Robert K. Meyer
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 22 (1). 1993.
    The Logic R4 is obtained by adding the axiom □(A v B) → (◇A v □B) to the modal relevant logic NR. We produce a model theory for this logic and show completeness. We also show that there is a natural embedding of a Kripke model for S4 in each R4 model structure
  •  42
    The incompleteness of RGL
    Studia Logica 65 (3): 315-322. 2000.
    RGLis a version of the modal logic GLbased on the relevant logic R. It is shown that the class of RKframes that verify all theorems of RGLalso verify a scheme that we call (!). If RGLhas (!) as a theorem, however, it is not a relevant logic. I go on to show that not all instances of (!) are theorems of RGL, hence this logic is not complete over any class of RKframes.
  •  55
    Semantics for relevance logic with identity
    Studia Logica 51 (1). 1992.
    Models are constructed for a variety of systems of quantified relevance logic with identity. Models are given for systems with different principles governing the transitivity of identity and substitution, and the relative merits of these principles are discussed. The models in this paper are all extensions of the semantics of Fine's Semantics for Quantified Relevance Logic (Journal of Philosophical Logic 17 (1988)).
  •  86
    Special-issue book review
    Philosophia Mathematica 4 (2): 198-202. 1996.
  •  98
    “Four-Valued” Semantics for the Relevant Logic R
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 33 (3): 327-341. 2004.
    This paper sets out two semantics for the relevant logic R based on Dunn's four-valued semantics for first-degree entailments. Unlike Routley's semantics for weak relevant logics, they do not use two ternary accessibility relations. Unlike Restall's semantics, they capture all of R. But there is a catch. Both of the present semantics are neighbourhood semantics, that is, they include sets of propositions in the specification of their frames
  •  28
    Even dialetheists should hate contradictions
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 78 (4). 2000.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  37
    CE is not a conservative extension of E
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 29 (3): 263-275. 2000.
    The logic CE (for "Classical E") results from adding Boolean negation to Anderson and Belnap's logic E. This paper shows that CE is not a conservative extension of E
  •  158
    A relevant theory of conditionals
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 24 (6). 1995.
    In this paper we set out a semantics for relevant (counterfactual) conditionals. We combine the Routley-Meyer semantics for relevant logic with a semantics for conditionals based on selection functions. The resulting models characterize a family of conditional logics free from fallacies of relevance, in particular counternecessities and conditionals with necessary consequents receive a non-trivial treatment
  •  89
    On S
    Studia Logica 53 (1). 1994.
    The sentential logic S extends classical logic by an implication-like connective. The logic was first presented by Chellas as the smallest system modelled by contraining the Stalnaker-Lewis semantics for counterfactual conditionals such that the conditional is effectively evaluated as in the ternary relations semantics for relevant logics. The resulting logic occupies a key position among modal and substructural logics. We prove completeness results and study conditions for proceeding from one f…Read more
  • The Semantic Completeness Of Rk
    Reports on Mathematical Logic 3-10. 1992.
    This paper extends the argument of Mares, ``Classically Complete Modal Relevant Logics'' Zeitschrift fur mathematische Logik und Grundlagen der Mathematik, to show that the system RK is complete over an Extension of the Routley-Meyer semantics.
  •  81
  •  114
    Relevant Logic and the Philosophy of Mathematics
    Philosophy Compass 7 (7): 481-494. 2012.
    This paper sets out three programmes that attempt to use relevant logic as the basis for a philosophy of mathematics. Although these three programmes do not exhaust the possible approaches to mathematics through relevant logic, they are fairly representative of the current state of the field. The three programmes are compared and their relative strengths and weaknesses set out. At the end of the paper I examine the consequences of adopting each programme for the realist debate about mathematical…Read more
  •  11
    Papers From Advances In Modal Logic, Volume 1 (review)
    Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 8 (1): 95-96. 2002.