•  180
    A work in the history of systematic philosophy that is itself animated by a systematic philosophic aspiration, this book by one of the most prominent American ...
  •  172
  •  168
    Unsuccessful semantics
    Analysis 54 (3): 175-178. 1994.
  •  161
    Action, norms, and practical reasoning
    Philosophical Perspectives 12 127-139. 1998.
  •  154
    Leibniz and degrees of perception
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 19 (4): 447-479. 1981.
    An examination of leibniz's doctrines of expressive degrees of perception suggest on textual grounds that representations are characterized as more or less 'distinct' or 'confused' in three different senses, Corresponding to the scope of content represent"ed", The degree of awareness accompanying the represent"ing" of that content, And the internal articulation of the idea expressed by such a representation. Following leibniz's rationalistic strategy of explaining representation in terms of infe…Read more
  •  151
    Rorty and His Critics
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2000.
    Essays, written by thirteen of the most distinguished living philosophers, together with Rorty's substantial replies to each, and other new material by him, offer by far the most thorough and thoughtful discussion of the work of the thinker who has been called "the most interesting philosopher alive."
  •  151
    From German Idealism to American Pragmatism – and Back
    In Stefano Bacin, Alfredo Ferrarin, Claudio La Rocca & Margit Ruffing (eds.), Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht. Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses, De Gruyter. pp. 107-126. 2013.
    Developments over the past four decades have secured Immanuel Kant’s status as being for contemporary philosophers what the sea was for Swinburne: the great, gray mother of us all. And Kant mattered as much for the classical American pragmatists as he does for us today. But we look back at that sepia-toned age across an extended period during which Anglophone philosophy largely wrote Kant out of its canon. The founding ideology of Bertrand Russell and G.E. Moore, articulating the rationale and f…Read more
  •  146
    Conceptual content and discursive practice
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 81 (1): 13-35. 2010.
    This paper discusses the integrated approach to the semantics and pragmatics of language developed in my Making It Explicit . The core claim is that there are six consequential relations among commitments and entitlements that are sufficient for a practice exhibiting them to qualify as discursive, that is, as a practice of giving and asking for reasons, hence as one conferring genuinely conceptual content on the expressions, performances, and statuses that have scorekeeping significances in thos…Read more
  •  145
  •  140
    Responses to Pippin, Macbeth and Haugeland
    European Journal of Philosophy 13 (3). 2005.
  •  129
    Reason in philosophy: animating ideas
    Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. 2009.
    This is a paradigmatic work of contemporary philosophy.
  •  129
    Making it Explicit
    with Isaac Levi
    Journal of Philosophy 93 (3): 145. 1996.
  •  128
    Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism
    Philosophical Review 111 (2): 284. 2002.
    This is a book review of: Robert B. Brandom, Articulating Reasons: An Introduction to Inferentialism. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2000. Pp. 230.
  •  114
    Review: Knowledge and the social articulation of the space of reasons (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 55 (4): 895--908. 1995.
    In “Knowledge and the Internal” John McDowell presents a deep and interesting argument. I think everything he says is true and important. Still, there are a number of points that bear expanding on in order to be properly understood. So I want to say something about his point of departure: the idea of standings in the space of reasons. And I want to fill in further the picture at which he finally arrives, by saying how I think we ought to understand knowledge as a standing in the space of reasons…Read more
  •  114
    Dasein, the Being that Thematizes
    Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 5 (1-2): 1-38. 1997.
  •  112
    Pragmatism, Phenomenalism, and Truth Talk
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 12 (1): 75-93. 1988.
  •  111
  •  110
    The Significance of Complex Numbers for Frege's Philosophy of Mathematics
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 96 (1). 1996.
    Robert Brandom; XII*—The Significance of Complex Numbers for Frege's Philosophy of Mathematics1, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 96, Issue 1, 1
  •  102
    Perception and Rational ConstraintMind and World
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2): 369. 1998.
  •  99
    Replies to Honneth, McDowell, Pippin, and Stern
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 103 (3): 741-760. 2021.
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Volume 103, Issue 3, Page 741-760, November 2021.
  •  99
    Inference, expression, and induction
    Philosophical Studies 54 (2). 1988.
  •  96
    Replies (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (1): 189-204. 1997.
  •  87
    The Logic of Inconsistency: a study in nonstandard possible-world semantics and ontology
    American Philosophical Quarterly, Library of Philosophy 5 (1): 233-236. 1979.
  •  87
    Pragmatists have traditionally been enemies of representationalism but friends of naturalism, when naturalism is understood to pertain to human subjects, in the sense of Hume and Nietzsche. In this volume Huw Price presents his distinctive version of this traditional combination, as delivered in his René Descartes Lectures at Tilburg University in 2008. Price contrasts his view with other contemporary forms of philosophical naturalism, comparing it with other pragmatist and neo-pragmatist views …Read more
  •  78
    Semantic paradox of material implication
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 22 (2): 129-132. 1981.
  •  78
    Singular Terms and Sentential Sign Designs
    Philosophical Topics 15 (1): 125-167. 1987.
  •  77
    Replies
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 57 (1): 189-204. 1997.