•  101
    Pain as a folk psychological concept: A clinical perspective (review)
    Brain and Mind 1 (2): 193-207. 2000.
    This paper develops an instrumentalistic argumentagainst an eliminativist approach to using the folkconcept of pain in clinical medicine and draws someimplications for biomedical theories of pain. Thepaper argues that the folk concept of pain plays afundamental role in several aspects of clinicalmedicine, including the diagnosis and treatment ofdiseases and symptoms, relieving human suffering, andthe doctor-patient relationship. Since clinicians mustbe able to apply biomedical theories of pain i…Read more
  •  5
    Review of Nanoethics: Big Ethical Issues with Small Technology (review)
    Studies in Ethics, Law, and Technology 4 (2). 2010.
  •  41
    DNA Patents and Human Dignity
    Journal of Law, Medicine and Ethics 29 (2): 152-165. 2001.
    Those objecting to human DNA patenting frequently do so on the grounds that the practice violates or threatens human dignity. For example, from 1993 to 1994, more than thirty organizations representing indigenous peoples approved formal declarations objecting to the National Institutes of Health's bid to patent viral DNA taken from subjects in Papua New Guinea and the Solomon Islands. Although these were not patents on human DNA, the organizations argued that the patents could harm and exploit i…Read more
  •  23
    Unequal treatment of human research subjects
    Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 18 (1): 23-32. 2015.
    Unequal treatment of human research subjects is a significant ethical concern, because justice in research involving human subjects requires equal protection of rights and equal protection from harm and exploitation. Disputes sometimes arise concerning the issue of unequal treatment of research subjects. Allegedly unequal treatment occurs when subjects are treated differently and there is a genuine dispute concerning the appropriateness of equal treatment. Patently unequal treatment occurs when …Read more
  •  27
    Medical misinformation on the Web: mitigation or control?
    Acm Sigcas Computers and Society 28 (1): 35-37. 1998.
  •  19
    Promoting Public Trust: ESCROs Won't Fix the Problem of Stem Cell Tourism
    with Zubin Master
    American Journal of Bioethics 13 (1): 53-55. 2013.
    No abstract
  •  19
    Retracting Inconclusive Research: Lessons from the Séralini GM Maize Feeding Study
    Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics 28 (4): 621-633. 2015.
    In September 2012, Gilles-Eric Séralini and seven coauthors published an article in Food and Chemical Toxicology claiming that rats fed Roundup©-resistant genetically modified maize alone, genetically modified maize with Roundup©, or Roundup© for 2 years had a higher percentage of tumors and kidney and liver damage than normal controls. Shortly after this study was published, numerous scientists and several scientific organizations criticized the research as methodologically and ethically flawed…Read more
  •  40
    Convergent Realism and Approximate Truth
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992 421-434. 1992.
    I examine the role that approximate truth plays in arguments for convergent realism and diagnose some difficulties that face attempts to defend realism by employing this slippery concept. Approximate truth plays two important roles in convergent realism : it functions as a truth surrogate and it helps explain the success of science. I argue that approximate truth cannot perform both of these roles. If it adequately fulfills its role as a truth surrogate, then it cannot explain the success of sci…Read more
  •  35
    Institutional Conflicts of Interest in Academic Research
    Science and Engineering Ethics 25 (6): 1661-1669. 2015.
    Financial relationships in academic research can create institutional conflicts of interest because the financial interests of the institution or institutional officials may inappropriately influence decision-making. Strategies for dealing with institutional COIs include establishing institutional COI committees that involve the board of trustees in conflict review and management, developing policies that shield institutional decisions from inappropriate influences, and establishing private foun…Read more
  •  43
    The clinical investigator-subject relationship: a contextual approach
    Philosophy, Ethics, and Humanities in Medicine 4 16-. 2009.
    BackgroundThe nature of the relationship between a clinical investigator and a research subject has generated considerable debate because the investigator occupies two distinct roles: clinician and scientist. As a clinician, the investigator has duties to provide the patient with optimal care and undivided loyalty. As a scientist, the investigator has duties to follow the rules, procedures and methods described in the protocol.Results and conclusionIn this article, I present a contextual approac…Read more
  •  9
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (1): 119-121. 1987.
  •  53
    Critical discussion
    Erkenntnis 38 (2). 1993.
    InExplaining Science: A Cognitive Approach, Ronald Giere (1988), proposes what he calls a cognitive theory of science (p. 2). Giere intends his view to be a broadly scientific account employing the resources of the cognitive sciences (Giere, 1988, p. 2). This paper argues that Giere does not secure a firm foundation for a cognitive theory of science because he leaves the door wide open for social constructivist interpretations of his views. In order to avoid social constructivism, Giere needs to…Read more
  •  78
    This paper discusses a dispute concerning the ethics of research on preventing the perinatal transmission of HIV in developing nations. Critics of this research argue that it is unethical because it denies a proven treatment to placebo‐control groups. Since studies conducted in developed nations would not deny this treatment to subjects, the critics maintain that these experiments manifest a double standard for ethical research and that a single standard of ethics should apply to all research on…Read more
  •  21
    H5N1 Avian Flu Research and the Ethics of Knowledge
    Hastings Center Report 43 (2): 22-33. 2013.
    Scientists and policy‐makers have long understood that the products of research can often be used for good or evil. Nuclear fission research can be used to generate electricity or create a powerful bomb. Studies on the genetics of human populations can be used to understand relationships between different groups or to perpetuate racist ideologies. While the notion that scientific research often has beneficial and harmful uses has been discussed before, the threat of bioterrorism—a concern that h…Read more
  •  35
    Two articles published in Bioethics recently have explored the ways that bioethics can contribute to the climate change debate. Cheryl Cox Macpherson argues that bioethicists can play an important role in the climate change debate by helping the public to better understand the values at stake and the trade-offs that must be made in individual and social choices, and Sean Valles claims that bioethicists can contribute to the debate by framing the issues in terms of the public health impacts of cl…Read more
  •  28
    The idea that research with human participants should benefit society has become firmly entrenched in various regulations, policies, and guidelines, but there has been little in-depth analysis of this ethical principle in the bioethics literature. In this paper, I distinguish between strong and weak versions and the social benefits principle and examine six arguments for it. I argue that while it is always ethically desirable for research with human subjects to offer important benefits to societ…Read more
  •  6
    Punishing Medical Experts for Unethical Testimony
    Journal of Philosophy, Science and Law 4 45-71. 2004.
  •  29
    Adaptationist Explanations
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 20 (2): 193. 1989.
  •  9
    Replies to commentaries
    Bioethics 12 (4). 1998.
  •  50
    Difficulties with regulating sex selection
    American Journal of Bioethics 1 (1). 2001.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  45
    Waiving legal rights in research
    with Efthimios Parasidis
    Journal of Medical Ethics 40 (7): 475-478. 2014.
    The US federal research regulations prohibit informed consent, whether written or oral, from including provisions in which human subjects waive or appear to waive legal rights. We argue that policies that prevent human subjects from waiving legal rights in research can be ethically justified under the rationale of group, soft paternalism. These policies protect competent adults from making adverse decisions about health and legal matters that they may not understand fully. However, this rational…Read more
  •  49
    Of maize and men: Reproductive control and the threat to genetic diversity
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 25 (4). 2000.
    The genetic diversity argument (GDA) is one of the most commonly voiced objections to advances in reproductive and genetic technologies. According to the argument, scientific and technological developments in the realm of genetics and human reproduction will lead to lower genetic diversity, which will threaten the health and survivability of the human population. This discussion explicates and analyzes the GDA and challenges its empirical assumptions. It also discusses the possible significance …Read more
  •  21
    Review of Gene Transfer and the Ethics of First-in-Human Research (review)
    Studies in Ethics, Law, and Technology 5 (1). 2011.
  •  27
    Direct-to-Consumer Genomics, Social Networking, and Confidentiality
    American Journal of Bioethics 9 (6-7): 45-46. 2009.
    No abstract
  •  56
    The rebirth of rational morphology
    Acta Biotheoretica 42 (1): 1-14. 1994.
    This paper examines a new challenge to neo-Darwinism, a movement known as process structuralism. The process structuralist critique of neo-Darwinism holds 1) that there are general laws in biology and that biologists should search for these laws; 2) that there are general forms of morphology and development and that biologists should attempt to uncover these forms; 3) that organisms are unified wholes that cannot be understood without adopting a holistic perspective; and 4) that no special, caus…Read more
  •  83
    Limits on risks for healthy volunteers in biomedical research
    Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 33 (2): 137-149. 2012.
    Healthy volunteers in biomedical research often face significant risks in studies that offer them no medical benefits. The U.S. federal research regulations and laws adopted by other countries place no limits on the risks that these participants face. In this essay, I argue that there should be some limits on the risks for biomedical research involving healthy volunteers. Limits on risk are necessary to protect human participants, institutions, and the scientific community from harm. With the ex…Read more
  •  58
    Protection of human subjects and scientific progress: Can the two be reconciled?
    with Kathleen Cranley Glass, Stephen Olufemi Sodeke, Halley S. Faust, Rebecca Dresser, Nancy M. P. King, C. D. Herrera, David Orentlicher, and Lynn A. Jansen
    Hastings Center Report 36 (1): 4-9. 2006.
  •  35
    This Article does not have an abstract