Jonathan Lear

This is a database entry with public information about a philosopher who is not a registered user of PhilPeople.
  •  94
    XII*—Aristotelian Infinity
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 80 (1): 187-210. 1980.
    Jonathan Lear; XII*—Aristotelian Infinity, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 80, Issue 1, 1 June 1980, Pages 187–210, https://doi.org/10.1093/aris.
  • The force of irony
    In T. J. Smiley, Jonathan Lear & Alex Oliver (eds.), The Force of Argument: Essays in Honor of Timothy Smiley, Routledge. 2010.
  •  144
    The Disappearing 'We'
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 58 (1). 1984.
  •  61
    This paper argues that if one considers just a single clinical moment there may be no principled way to choose among different approaches to psychoanalytic technique. One must in addition take into account what Aristotle called the final cause of psychoanalysis, which this paper argues is freedom. However, freedom is itself an open-ended concept with many aspects that need to be explored and developed from a psychoanalytic perspective. This paper considers one analytic moment from the perspectiv…Read more
  •  151
    Response to Hubert Dreyfus and Nancy Sherman
    Philosophical Studies 144 (1). 2009.
    This paper tries to make clear what practical intelligibility is and how it is threatened at times of cultural breakdown or devastation. It argues that it is easy to overlook a breakdown in practical intelligibility because there is a tendency to frame the problems in terms of theoretical reason. Once one gets clear on what the threat to intelligibility is (and what it is not) one can see fairly straightforward ways to respond to the comments made by Dreyfus and Sherman.
  •  101
    Psychoanalysis and the idea of a moral psychology: Memorial to Bernard Williams' philosophy
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 47 (5). 2004.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  24
    Review: Avowal and Unfreedom (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (2). 2004.
    1. In Authority and Estrangement, Richard Moran shows us with marvelous clarity how our capacity for avowal is constitutive of our freedom as rational agents. But philosophers also need to acknowledge that avowal plays a crucial role in keeping us unfree. This eludes Moran’s attention, I suspect, because he uses the therapeutic situation as a contrasting paradigm to our ordinary capacity for avowal.
  •  161
    After this, nothing happened -- Ethics at the horizon -- Critique of abysmal reasoning.
  •  48
    Philosophy as a Humanistic Discipline (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 104 (10): 546-550. 2007.
  •  19
    Moral Objectivity
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Lecture Series 17 135-170. 1984.
    Morality exercises a deep and questionable influence on the way we live our lives. The influence is deep both because moral injunctions are embedded in our psyches long before we can reflect on their status and because even after we become reflective agents, the question of how we should live our lives among others is intimately bound up with the more general question of how we should live our lives: our stance toward morality and our conception of our lives as having significance are of a piece…Read more
  •  82
    Open minded: working out the logic of the soul
    Harvard University Press. 1998.
    Explores the relationship between philosophers' and psychoanalysts' attempts to discover how man thinks and perceives himself
  •  146
    Leaving the world alone
    Journal of Philosophy 79 (7): 382-403. 1982.
  •  122
    Katharsis
    Phronesis 33 (1): 297-326. 1988.
  •  46
    In this brilliant book, Jonathan Lear argues that Freud posits love as a basic force in nature, one that makes individuation -- the condition for psychological health and development -- possible.
  •  23
    L'efficacia del mito nella "Repubblica" di Platone
    Iride: Filosofia e Discussione Pubblica 16 (3): 445-466. 2003.
  •  22
    IV-Integrating the Non-Rational Soul
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 114 (1pt1): 75-101. 2014.
  •  88
    Integrating the Non‐Rational Soul
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 114 (1pt1): 75-101. 2014.
    Aristotelian theory of virtue and of happiness assumes a moral psychology in which the parts of the soul, rational and non-rational, can communicate well with each other. But if Aristotle cannot give a robust account of what communicating well consists in, he faces Bernard Williams's charge that his moral psychology collapses into a moralizing psychology, assuming the very categories it seeks to vindicate. This paper examines the problem and proposes a way forward, namely, that Freudian psychoan…Read more
  •  53
    Freud
    Routledge. 2005.
    In this fully updated second edition, Jonathan Lear clearly introduces and assesses all of Freud's thought, focusing on those areas of philosophy on which Freud is acknowledged to have had a lasting impact. These include the philosophy of mind, free will and determinism, rationality, the nature of the self and subjectivity, and ethics and religion. He also considers some of the deeper issues and problems Freud engaged with, brilliantly illustrating their philosophical significance: human sexuali…Read more
  •  36
    Happiness, death, and the remainder of life
    Harvard University Press. 2000.
    But if, with Jonathan Lear, we scrutinize these thinkers' attempts to explain human behavior in terms of a higher principle--whether happiness or death--the ...
  •  28
    Human Morality by Samuel Scheffler (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 90 (4): 205-211. 1993.
  •  9
    Critical Notice
    Mind 104 (416). 1995.
  •  22
    Das körperliche Ich. Zum Gedenken an Richard Wollheim
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 54 (5): 743-750. 2006.
    Ein zentrales Anliegen Richard Wollheims war es, Erkenntnisse der Psychoanalyse für die Philosophie fruchtbar zu machen. Mit dem Konzept des „körperlichen Ich” verweist Wollheim auf die mannigfaltigen Aspekte der körperlichen Repräsentation geistiger Zustände. Sei es, dass psychische Zustände durch körperliche Metaphern ausgedrückt werden, sei es, dass sie als physische Ereignisse repräsentiert oder halluziniert werden und als solche ihre Wirkung entfalten. Diese Repräsentationen eröffnen überra…Read more
  •  273
    Ethics, mathematics and relativism
    Mind 92 (365): 38-60. 1983.
  •  152
    Aristotle’s Philosophy of Mathematics
    Philosophical Review 91 (2): 161-192. 1982.
    Whether aristotle wrote a work on mathematics as he did on physics is not known, and sources differ. this book attempts to present the main features of aristotle's philosophy of mathematics. methodologically, the presentation is based on aristotle's "posterior analytics", which discusses the nature of scientific knowledge and procedure. concerning aristotle's views on mathematics in particular, they are presented with the support of numerous references to his extant works. his criticism of his p…Read more
  •  97
    A case for irony
    Harvard University Press. 2011.
    " Here Jonathan Lear argues that irony is one of the tools we use to live seriously, to get the hang of becoming human.
  •  16
    Avowal and Unfreedom
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69 (2): 448-454. 2004.
    1. In Authority and Estrangement, Richard Moran shows us with marvelous clarity how our capacity for avowal is constitutive of our freedom as rational agents. But philosophers also need to acknowledge that avowal plays a crucial role in keeping us unfree. This eludes Moran’s attention, I suspect, because he uses the therapeutic situation as a contrasting paradigm to our ordinary capacity for avowal.
  •  70
    Aristotle and Logical Theory
    Cambridge University Press. 1980.
    Aristotle was the first and one of the greatest logicians. He not only devised the first system of formal logic, but also raised many fundamental problems in the philosophy of logic. In this book, Dr Lear shows how Aristotle's discussion of logical consequence, validity and proof can contribute to contemporary debates in the philosophy of logic. No background knowledge of Aristotle is assumed.
  • Aristotle and Logical Theory
    Philosophical Quarterly 32 (126): 76-86. 1982.