•  70
  •  119
    The Four-Dimensional World
    Analysis 37 (1): 32-39. 1976.
    This paper defends the view of continuants as 'four-dimensional worms' against an argument of Geach's. This is to the effect that if continuants are four-dimensional worms then their stages either do, or do not, fall under the very general terms satisfied by the continuants themselves (a stage of a man either is, or is not, a man); but that either alternative is untenable. I try to show how the former alternative may be defended by appealing to some of Geach's own ideas about identity; then go o…Read more
  •  219
    Count Nouns and Mass Nouns
    Analysis 38 (4): 167-172. 1978.
    The paper argues that one distinction between concrete count nouns and concrete mass nouns is that geach's derelativization thesis is valid for the former but not valid for the latter. That is, Where 'f' is a concrete count noun 'x is (an) f' means 'for some y, X is the same f as y', But where 'f' is a concrete mass noun this is not so; rather, In this case, 'x is f' is tantamount to 'for some y, X is the f of y'. It is further suggested that abstract nouns are in this respect to be grouped with…Read more
  •  84
    Rigid Designation
    Analysis 39 (4): 174-182. 1979.
  •  242
    On the notion of a sortal concept
    Philosophical Quarterly 28 (110): 58-64. 1978.
  •  51
    Relative identity: a reply to Nicholas Griffin
    Mind 89 (353): 96-98. 1980.
    In the October 1978 issue of Mind, Nicholas Griffin puts forward a criticism of one of my arguments in 'Wiggins on Identity'. Although I would not now wish to defend everything I said in that paper, the argument Griffin attacks still seems to me to be a good one. In what follows, I explain why I think his criticism fails to strike home.
  •  70
    Reply to Garrett
    Analysis 46 (4): 205-211. 1986.
  •  183
    Are there vague objects?
    Analysis 64 (2): 131-134. 2004.
  •  103
    McKinsey-brown survives
    Analysis 60 (4): 353-356. 2000.
  •  211
    Relative Identity
    Philosophical Investigations 38 (1-2): 52-71. 2015.
    Examples suggest that one and the same A may be different Bs, and hence that there is some sort of incompleteness in the unqualified statement that x and y are the same which needs to be eliminated by answering the question “the same what?” One way to make this more precise is by appeal to Geach's idea that identity is relative. In this paper I evaluate Geach's relative identity thesis
  •  37
    Animalism Versus Lockeanism: A Current Controversy
    Philosophical Quarterly 48 (192): 302-318. 1998.
    My purpose is to explore the possible lines of reply available to a defender of the neo‐Lockean position on personal identity in response to the recently popular ‘animalist’ objection. I compare the animalist objection with an objection made to Locke by Bishop Butler, Thomas Reid and, in our own day, Sydney Shoemaker. I argue that the only possible response available to a defender of Locke against the Butler–Reid–Shoemaker objection is to reject Locke's official definition of a person as a think…Read more
  •  10
    VI*—Names and Belief
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 81 (1): 93-108. 1981.
    Harold Noonan; VI*—Names and Belief, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 81, Issue 1, 1 June 1981, Pages 93–108, https://doi.org/10.1093/aristotelia.
  •  1
  •  251
    The only X and Y principle
    Analysis 45 (1): 79-83. 1985.
  •  66
    Fregean Thoughts
    Philosophical Quarterly 34 (136): 205-224. 1984.
  •  101
    Two Boxing is not the Rational Option
    Ratio 29 (2): 168-183. 2016.
    In the standard Newcomb scenario two-boxing is not the rational act and, in general, in Newcomb-style cases the ‘two-boxing’ choice is not the rational act. Hence any decision theory which recommends two-boxing is unacceptable.
  •  30
    Can one thing become two?
    Philosophical Studies 33 (3): 203-227. 1978.
    I shall argue that (in a sense to be explained) one thing can become two.
  •  15
    Mass Terms: Some Philosophical Problems, edited by F. J. Pelletier (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 30 (120): 259-260. 1980.
  •  91
    Reply to Simons on Coincidence
    Mind 95 (377): 100-104. 1986.
  •  7
    Bob Hale, "Abstract Objects" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 39 (56): 354. 1989.
  •  37
    Saul Kripke is one of the most important philosophers of the twentieth century. His most celebrated work, Naming and Necessity , makes arguably the most important contribution to the philosophy of language and metaphysics in recent years. Asking fundamental questions – how do names refer to things in the world? Do objects have essential properties? What are natural kind terms and to what do they refer? – he challenges prevailing theories of language and conceptions of metaphysics, especially the…Read more
  •  102
    A Flaw in Kripke’s Modal Argument?
    Philosophia 41 (3): 841-846. 2013.
    The response to Kripke’s modal argument I wish to propose appeals to the distinction between indicative descriptions, i.e., descriptions formed using indicative verb forms, and what I shall call subjunctive descriptions, descriptions formed using non-indicative verb forms used in subjunctive conditionals. The contrast is between ‘the person who is richer than anyone else in the world’ and ‘the person who would have been richer than anyone else in the world’. The response to Kripke’s modal argume…Read more
  •  49
    Wiggins on identity
    Mind 85 (340): 559-575. 1976.
  •  406
    Coincidence comes in two varieties – permanent and temporary. Moderate monism is the position that permanent coincidence, but not temporary coincidence, entails identity. Extreme monism is the position that even temporary coincidence entails identity. Pluralists are opponents of monism tout court. The intuitively obvious, commonsensical position is moderate monism. It is therefore important to see if it can be sustained.
  •  429
    Personal pronoun revisionism (so-called by Olson, E. 2007. What are We? A Study in Personal Ontology. Oxford: Oxford University Press) is a response to the problem of the thinking animal on behalf of the neo-Lockean theorist. Many worry about this response. The worry rests on asking the wrong question, namely: how can two thinkers that are so alike differ in this way in their cognitive capacities? This is the wrong question because they don't. The right question is: how can they fail to be the s…Read more
  •  88
    Substance, Identity and Time
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 62 79-100. 1988.
  •  2
    The self and personal identity
    In Alan Bailey & Dan O'Brien (eds.), The Continuum Companion to Hume, Continuum. pp. 167. 2012.