•  319
    Triviality arguments against functionalism
    Philosophical Studies 145 (2). 2009.
    “Triviality arguments” against functionalism in the philosophy of mind hold that the claim that some complex physical system exhibits a given functional organization is either trivial or has much less content than is usually supposed. I survey several earlier arguments of this kind, and present a new one that overcomes some limitations in the earlier arguments. Resisting triviality arguments is possible, but requires functionalists to revise popular views about the “autonomy” of functional descr…Read more
  •  102
    Sender-Receiver Systems within and between Organisms
    Philosophy of Science 81 (5): 866-878. 2014.
    Drawing on models of communication due to Lewis and Skyrms, I contrast sender-receiver systems as they appear within and between organisms, and as they function in the bridging of space and time. Within the organism, memory can be seen as the sending of messages over time, communication between stages as opposed to spatial parts. Psychological memory and genetic memory are compared with respect to their relations to a sender-receiver model. Some puzzles about “genetic information” can be resolve…Read more
  •  53
    Senders, Receivers, and Symbolic Artifacts
    Biological Theory 12 (4): 275-286. 2017.
    A “sender–receiver” framework based on models developed in several fields can provide a general treatment of communicative and symbolic phenomena, replacing traditional semiotic theories that have failed to live up to the hopes of their advocates. Sender–receiver models have mostly been applied to linguistic behavior, gestures, and other ephemeral interactions between individuals. I look at the application of this framework to enduring artifacts, including pictures, using indigenous rock art in …Read more
  •  52
    Signal, Decision, Action
    Journal of Philosophy 88 (12): 709. 1991.
  •  69
    Signs and Symbolic Behavior
    Biological Theory 9 (1): 78-88. 2014.
    Research in archaeology and anthropology on the evolution of modern patterns of human behavior often makes use of general theories of signs, usually derived from semiotics. Recent work generalizing David Lewis’ 1969 model of signaling provides a better theory of signs than those currently in use. This approach is based on the coevolution of behaviors of sign production and sign interpretation. I discuss these models and then look at applications to human prehistoric behavior, focusing on body or…Read more
  •  585
    Recurrent transient underdetermination and the glass half full (review)
    Philosophical Studies 137 (1). 2008.
    Kyle Stanford’s arguments against scientific realism are assessed, with a focus on the underdetermination of theory by evidence. I argue that discussions of underdetermination have neglected a possible symmetry which may ameliorate the situation.
  •  45
    Reply to Rosenberg
    Biology and Philosophy 33 (3-4): 19. 2018.
    I respond to two of the main arguments in Rosenberg’s commentary on “Mind, Matter, and Metabolism.” Rosenberg’s claim that metabolic activities are “modularized” in a way that sets them apart from cognitive processes is not true given the broad sense of the “metabolic” employed in my paper, and contemporary neuroscience, including the work on navigation cited by Rosenberg, has begun to yield an understanding of subjectivity and “point of view.”
  •  33
    R. G. Millikan: "Language, Thought, and Other Biological Categories" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (n/a): 556. 1988.
  •  42
    Mercier and Sperber (M&S) claim that the main function of reasoning is to generate support for conclusions derived unconsciously. An alternative account holds that reasoning has a deliberative function even though it is an internalized analogue of public discourse. We sketch this alternative and compare it with M&S's in the light of the empirical phenomena they discuss
  • References
    In Philosophy of Biology, Princeton University Press. pp. 159-178. 2013.
  •  41
    Procrustes probably
    Philosophical Studies 95 (1-2): 175-181. 1999.
  •  8
    Some central ideas associated with developmental systems theory are outlined for non-specialists. These ideas concern the nature of biological development, the alleged distinction between “genetic” and “environmental” traits, the relations between organism and environment, and evolutionary processes. I also discuss some criticisms of the DST approach.
  •  115
    In the beginning there was information?
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 80 101239. 2020.
  •  141
    Individuality, subjectivity, and minimal cognition
    Biology and Philosophy 31 (6): 775-796. 2016.
    The paper links discussions of two topics: biological individuality and the simplest forms of mentality. I discuss several attempts to locate the boundary between metabolic activity and ‘minimal cognition.’ I then look at differences between the kinds of individuality present in unicellular life, multicellular life in general, and animals of several kinds. Nervous systems, which are clearly relevant to cognition and subjectivity, also play an important role in the form of individuality seen in a…Read more
  •  70
    Is it a revolution?
    Biology and Philosophy 22 (3): 429-437. 2007.
    Jablonka and Lamb's claim that evolutionary biology is undergoing a ‘revolution’ is queried. But the very concept of revolutionary change has uncertain application to a field organized in the manner of contemporary biology. The explanatory primacy of sequence properties is also discussed.
  •  101
    Information, arbitrariness, and selection: Comments on Maynard Smith
    Philosophy of Science 67 (2): 202-207. 2000.
    Maynard Smith is right that one of the most striking features of contemporary biology is the ever-increasing prominence of the concept of information, along with related concepts like representation, programming, and coding. Maynard Smith is also right that this is surely a phenomenon which philosophers of science should examine closely. We should try to understand exactly what sorts of theoretical commitment are made when biological systems are described in these terms, and what connection ther…Read more
  •  149
    Indication and adaptation
    Synthese 92 (2): 283-312. 1992.
    This paper examines the relationship between a family of concepts involving reliable correlation, and a family of concepts involving adaptation and biological function, as these concepts are used in the naturalistic semantic theory of Dretske's "Explaining Behavior." I argue that Dretske's attempt to marry correlation and function to produce representation fails, though aspects of his failure point the way forward to a better theory.
  •  1
    Index
    In Philosophy of Biology, Princeton University Press. pp. 179-188. 2013.
  •  262
    Group fitness and multi-level selection: Replies to commentaries (review)
    with Benjamin Kerr
    Biology and Philosophy 17 (4): 539-549. 2002.
  •  66
    Gradualism and the Evolution of Experience
    Philosophical Topics 48 (1): 201-220. 2020.
    In evolution, large-scale changes that involve the origin of complex new traits occur gradually, in a broad sense of the term. This principle applies to the origin of subjective or felt experience. I respond to difficulties that have been raised for a gradualist view in this area, and sketch a scenario for the gradual evolution of subjective experience, drawing on recent research into early nervous system evolution.
  •  139
    Some central ideas associated with developmental systems theory (DST) are outlined for non-specialists. These ideas concern the nature of biological development, the alleged distinction between "genetic" and "environmental" traits, the relations between organism and environment, and evolutionary processes. I also discuss some criticisms of the DST approach
  •  169
    Evolving Across the Explanatory Gap
    Philosophy, Theory, and Practice in Biology 11 (1): 1-13. 2019.
    One way to express the most persistent part of the mind-body problem is to say that there is an “explanatory gap” between the physical and the mental. The gap is not usually taken to apply to all of the mental, but to subjective experience, the mind’s “qualitative” features, or what is now referred to as “phenomenal consciousness.” The “gap” formulation is due to Joseph Levine. He acknowledged the appeal of intuitions of separability between physical facts, of any kind we can envisage, and this …Read more
  •  130
    Dewey on naturalism, realism and science
    Proceedings of the Philosophy of Science Association 2002 (3). 2002.
    An interpretation of John Dewey’s views about realism, science, and naturalistic philosophy is presented. Dewey should be seen as an unorthodox realist, with respect to both general metaphysical debates about realism and with respect to debates about the aims and achievements of science.
  •  71
  •  51
    Dewey and the Question of Realism
    Noûs 47 (4): 73-89. 2013.
    An interpretation is given of John Dewey's views about “realism” in metaphysics, and of how these views relate to contemporary debates. Dewey rejected standard formulations of realism as a general metaphysical position, and interpreters have often been taken him to be sympathetic to some form of verificationism or constructivism. I argue that these interpretations are mistaken, as Dewey's unease with standard formulations of realism comes from his philosophical emphasis on intelligent control of…Read more