• Real 3 intentionality (Why intentionality involves the conscience)
    Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 27 (3): 35-69. 2008.
  •  127
    The Unhelpfulness of Indeterminism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 149-155. 2000.
  • Freedom and Belief
    Behaviorism 17 (2): 177-179. 1989.
  •  987
    ‘the Self’
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 4 (5-6): 405-428. 1997.
    Recommends an approach to the philosophical problem about the existence and nature of the self in which the author models the problem of the self rather than attempting to model the self. It is suggested that the sense of the self is the source in experience of the philosophical problem of the self. The first question to ask is the phenomenological question: What is the nature of the sense of the self? But this, in the first instance, is best taken as a question explicitly about human beings: as…Read more
  •  37
    Owning the Past Reply to Stokes
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 18 (3-4): 3-4. 2011.
  •  200
    The evident connexion: Hume on personal identity
    Oxford University Press. 2011.
    This lucid book is the first to be wholly dedicated to Hume's theory of personal identity, and presents a bold new interpretation which bears directly on ...
  •  28
    I_– _Sydney Shoemaker: Self, Body, and Coincidence
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 73 (1): 287-306. 1999.
    [Sydney Shoemaker] A major objection to the view that the relation of persons to human animals is coincidence rather than identity is that on this view the human animal will share the coincident person's physical properties, and so should share its mental properties. But while the same physical predicates are true of the person and the human animal, the difference in the persistence conditions of these entities implies that there will be a difference in the properties ascribed by these predicate…Read more
  •  416
    Mental ballistics or the involuntariness of spontaniety
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103 (3): 227-257. 2003.
    It is sometimes said that reasoning, thought and judgement essentially involve action. It is sometimes said that they involve spontaneity, where spontaneity is taken to be connected in some constitutive way with action-intentional, voluntary and indeed free action. There is, however, a fundamental respect in which reason, thought and judgement neither are nor can be a matter of action; and any spontaneity they involve can be connected with freedom only when the word 'freedom' is used in the Spin…Read more
  •  95
    The Self
    In Brian McLaughlin, Ansgar Beckermann & Sven Walter (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mind, Oxford University Press. 2009.
  •  18
    I and I: immunity to error through misidentification of the subject
    In S. Prosser and F. Recanati (ed.), Immunity to Error Through Misidentification: New Essays, Cambridge University Press. pp. 202-223. 2012.
    I argue for the following claims: [1] all uses of I are absolutely immune to error through misidentification relative to I. [2] no genuine use of I can fail to refer. Nevertheless [3] I isn’t univocal: it doesn’t always refer to the same thing, or kind of thing, even in the thought or speech of a single person. This is so even though [4] I always refers to its user, the subject of experience who speaks or thinks, and although [5] if I’m thinking about something specifically as myself, I can’t fa…Read more
  •  192
    Real Materialism: And Other Essays
    Oxford University Press. 2008.
    Real Materialism is a collection of highly original essays on a set of related topics in philosophy of mind and metaphysics: consciousness and the mind-body problem; our knowledge of the world; the nature of the self or subject; free will and moral responsibility; the nature of thought and intentionality; causation and David Hume.
  •  332
    Free will
    In Edward Craig (ed.), The Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Routledge. 1998.
    ‘Free will’ is the conventional name of a topic that is best discussed without reference to the will. It is a topic in metaphysics and ethics as much as in the philosophy of mind. Its central questions are ‘What is it to act (or choose) freely?’, and ‘What is it to be morally responsible for one’s actions (or choices)?’ These two questions are closely connected, for it seems clear that freedom of action is a necessary condition of moral responsibility, even if it is not sufficient
  •  135
    ‘The Secrets of All Hearts’: Locke on Personal Identity
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 76 111-141. 2015.
    Many think John Locke's account of personal identity is inconsistent and circular. It's neither of these things. The root causes of the misreading are [i] the mistake of thinking that Locke uses 'consciousness' to mean memory, [ii] failure to appreciate the importance of the ‘concernment’ that always accompanies ‘consciousness’, on Locke's view, [iii] a tendency to take the term 'person', in Locke's text, as if it were only some kind of fundamental sortal term like ‘human being’ or ‘thinking thi…Read more
  •  103
    Free Agents
    Philosophical Topics 32 371-402. 2004.
    In this paper I try to give an account of necessary and sufficient conditions of true freedom of action, of true or ultimate responsibility, even while acknowledging that such ultimate responsibility is impossible, because one of the conditions—being causa sui, or absolutely self-originating—is unfulfillable. I consider various forms of the ‘able-to-choose’ condition on freedom, and summarize the argument in part III of my book Freedom and Belief for the seemingly paradoxical claim that one of t…Read more
  •  231
    Red and 'red'
    Synthese 78 (February): 193-232. 1989.
    THIS PAPER ARGUES FOR THE CLAIM THAT ALTHOUGH COLOUR WORDS LIKE 'RED' ARE, ESSENTIALLY, 'PHENOMENAL-QUALITY' WORDS—I.E., WORDS FOR PROPERTIES WHOSE WHOLE AND ESSENTIAL NATURE CAN BE AND IS FULLY REVEALED IN SENSORY EXPERIENCE, GIVEN ONLY THE QUALITATIVE CHARACTER THAT THAT EXPERIENCE HAS—STILL 'RED' CANNOT BE SUPPOSED TO BE A WORD THAT PICKS OUT OR DENOTES ANY PARTICULAR PHENOMENAL QUALITY. THE ARGUMENT RESTS ESSENTIALLY ON THE SUPPOSITION, OFTEN DISCUSSED UNDER THE HEADING OF THE 'COLOR-SPECTRU…Read more
  •  87
    The impossibility of ultimate responsibility?
    In Richard Swinburne (ed.), Free Will and Modern Science, Oup/british Academy. 2011.
    This chapter argues that the mere fact that a decision has not been fully caused by previous events suggests that these are simply random events for which a person cannot be properly held morally responsible. Whatever the laws governing the formations of our decisions, it is simply not possible that a person can be morally responsible for their actions. For either they are caused to do what they do by events outside their control, or their actions are the result of random processes.
  •  305
    Consciousness, free will, and the unimportance of determinism
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 32 (March): 3-27. 1989.
    This article begins with some brief reflexions on the definition of determinism (II), on the notion of the subject of experience (III), and on the relation between conscious experience and brain events (IV). The main discussion (V?XIII) focuses on the traditional view, endorsed by Honderich in his book A Theory of Determinism, that the truth of determinism poses some special threat to our ordinary conception of ourselves as morally responsible free agents (and also to our ?life?hopes'). It is ar…Read more
  •  1314
    The Bounds of freedom
    In Robert Kane (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Free Will, Oxford University Press. pp. 441-460. 2001.
    The shortest form of the Basic Argument against free will and moral responsibility runs as follows: [1] When you act, you do what you do—in the situation in which you find yourself—because of the way you are. [2] If you do what you do because of the way you are, then in order to be fully and ultimately responsible for what you do you must be fully and ultimately responsible for the way you are. But [3] You cannot be fully and ultimately responsible for the way you are. So [4] You cannot be fully…Read more
  •  2274
    Mind and Being: The Primacy of Panpsychism
    In Godehard Brüntrup & Ludwig Jaskolla (eds.), Panpsychism: Contemporary Perspectives, Oxford University Press. pp. 000-00. 2016.
    I endorse a 12-word metaphysics. [1] Stoff ist Kraft ≈ being is energy. [2] Wesen ist Werden ≈ being is becoming. [3] Sein ist Sosein ≈ being is qualit[ativit]y. [4] Ansichsein ist Fürsichsein ≈ being is mind. [1]–[3] are plausible metaphysical principles and unprejudiced consideration of what we know about concrete reality obliges us to favor [4], i.e. panpsychism or panexperientialism, above all other positive substantive proposals. For [i] panpsychism is the most ontologically parsimonious vi…Read more
  •  26
    Knowledge of the World 1
    Philosophical Issues 12 (1): 146-175. 2002.
  •  72
  •  67
    Humeanism
    Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1 (1): 96--102. 2015.
    ABSTRACT ABSTRACT: In metaphysics, the adjective ‘Humean’ is used to describe positions that deny the existence of any necessary connection or causal influence in concrete reality. This usage has been significantly reinforced by David Lewis’s employment of ‘Humean’ in the phrase ‘Humean supervenience’. It is, however, not at all clear that this usage is appropriate. Lewis himself raised a doubt about it.
  •  34
    Reale intentionalität V.2: Warum impliziert intentionalität bewusstsein?
    Synthesis Philosophica 20 (2): 279-297. 2005.
    Intentionalität ist ein essenziell mentales, essenziell ereignishaftes und essenziell auf Erfahrung beruhendes Phänomen. Jeder Versuch, der die Intentionalität charakterisieren will und sie von der bewussten Erfahrung entkoppelt, sieht sich zwei unüberwindbaren Problemen gegenübergestellt. Erstens muss man einräumen, dass beinahe alles Intentionalität besitzt – bis hin zu den subatomaren Partikeln. Zweitens hat dies zur Folge, dass alles, was Intentionalität besitzt, viel zuviel davon besitzt – …Read more
  •  1
    Freedom and Belief
    Mind 97 (387): 481-484. 1988.
  •  259
    The self and the SESMET
    Journal of Consciousness Studies 6 (4): 99-135. 2002.
    Response to commentaries on keynote article
  •  11
    Episodische Ethik
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 56 (5): 651-675. 2008.
    Der Beitrag unterscheidet zwischen episodischen und diachronischen Persönlichkeiten. Episodische Persönlichkeiten leben emotional stark in der Gegenwart und verfügen im Gegensatz zu diachronischen Persönlichkeiten nicht über ein Narrativ, welches sie ihre Gegenwart und Vergangenheit als eine Einheit empfinden lässt. Der Autor führt vor, dass episodische Persönlichkeiten trotz ihres psychologisch nur schwach ausgeprägten Verhältnisses zu ihrer eigenen Vergangenheit moralfähig sind
  •  197
    Postface
    Princeton. 2014 [2011].