•  42
    The question of personal identity—what makes a person the same person over time—is puzzling. Through the course of a life, someone might undergo a dramatic alteration in personality, radically change her values, lose almost all of her memories, and undergo significant changes in her physical appearance. Given all of these potential changes, why should we be inclined to regard her as the same person? Battlestar Galactica presents us with an even bigger puzzle: What makes a Cylon the same Cylon ov…Read more
  •  2
    Editorial
    Philosophical Studies 163 (1): 1-1. 2013.
  •  964
    Imaginative Vividness
    Journal of the American Philosophical Association 3 (1): 32-50. 2017.
    How are we to understand the phenomenology of imagining? Attempts to answer this question often invoke descriptors concerning the “vivacity” or “vividness” of our imaginative states. Not only are particular imaginings often phenomenologically compared and contrasted with other imaginings on grounds of how vivid they are, but such imaginings are also often compared and contrasted with perceptions and memories on similar grounds. Yet however natural it may be to use “vividness” and cognate term…Read more
  •  316
    Shoemaker, self-blindness and Moore's paradox
    Philosophical Quarterly 53 (210): 39-48. 2003.
    I show how the 'innersense' (quasiperceptual) view of introspection can be defended against Shoemaker's influential 'argument from selfblindness'. If introspection and perception are analogous, the relationship between beliefs and introspective knowledge of them is merely contingent. Shoemaker argues that this implies the possibility that agents could be selfblind, i.e., could lack any introspective awareness of their own mental states. By invoking Moore's paradox, he rejects this possibility. B…Read more
  •  43
    Imagination and the Imaginary, by Kathleen Lennon (review)
    Mind 125 (500): 1244-1251. 2016.
    Imagination and the Imaginary, by LennonKathleen. London : Routledge, 2015. Pp. viii + 145.
  •  36
    Captain Fantastic (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 75 112-113. 2016.
  •  335
    Qualia realism
    Philosophical Studies 104 (2). 2001.
    Philosophical Studies 104: 143-162 (2001).
  •  1668
    The Heterogeneity of the Imagination
    Erkenntnis 78 (1): 141-159. 2013.
    Imagination has been assigned an important explanatory role in a multitude of philosophical contexts. This paper examines four such contexts: mindreading, pretense, our engagement with fiction, and modal epistemology. Close attention to each of these contexts suggests that the mental activity of imagining is considerably more heterogeneous than previously realized. In short, no single mental activity can do all the explanatory work that has been assigned to imagining
  •  53
    Knowledge and Mind (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 25 (1): 98-101. 2002.
  •  187
    How to believe in qualia
    In Edmond Wright (ed.), The Case for Qualia, Mit Press. pp. 285--298. 2008.
    in The Case for Qualia,ed. by Edmond Wright , MIT Press (2008), pp. 285-298.
  •  252
    As persons, we are importantly different from all other creatures in the universe. But in what, exactly, does this difference consist? What kinds of entities are we, and what makes each of us the same person today that we were yesterday? Could we survive having all of our memories erased and replaced with false ones? What about if our bodies were destroyed and our brains were transplanted into android bodies, or if instead our minds were simply uploaded to computers? In this engaging and accessi…Read more
  •  1713
    The Puzzle of Imaginative Desire
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89 (3): 421-439. 2011.
    The puzzle of imaginative desire arises from the difficulty of accounting for the surprising behaviour of desire in imaginative activities such as our engagement with fiction and our games of pretend. Several philosophers have recently attempted to solve this puzzle by introducing a class of novel mental states—what they call desire-like imaginings or i-desires. In this paper, I argue that we should reject the i-desire solution to the puzzle of imaginative desire. The introduction of i-desires i…Read more
  •  1043
    From the perspective of many philosophers of mind in these early years of the 21st Century, the debate between dualism and physicalism has seemed to have stalled, if not to have come to a complete standstill. There seems to be no way to settle the basic clash of intuitions that underlies it. Recently however, a growing number of proponents of Russellian monism have suggested that their view promises to show us a new way forward. Insofar as Russellian monism might allow us to break out of the cur…Read more
  •  36
    Is Ignorance Bliss?
    In Sandra Shapshay (ed.), Bioethics at the movies, Johns Hopkins University Press. pp. 121. 2009.
  •  245
    The Irreducibility of Consciousness
    Disputatio 1 (19): 1-18. 2005.
    In this paper, by analyzing the Chalmers-Searle debate about Chalmers’ zombie thought experiment, I attempt to determine the implications that the irreducibility of consciousness has for the truth of materialism. While Chalmers claims that the irreducibility of consciousness forces us to embrace dualism, Searle claims that it has no deep metaphysical import and, in particular, that it is fully consistent with his materialist theory of mind. I argue that this disagreement hinges on the notion of …Read more
  •  41
    Metaphysics at the multiplex
    The Philosophers' Magazine 55 (55): 112-113. 2011.
    This is a brief review of the movie "Source Code."
  •  98
    Introspection
    Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2005.
    Introspection is the process by which someone comes to form beliefs about her own mental states. We might form the belief that someone else is happy on the basis of perception – for example, by perceiving her behavior. But a person typically does not have to observe her own behavior in order to determine whether she is happy. Rather, one makes this determination by introspecting
  •  2241
    According to representationalism, the phenomenal character of a mental state reduces to its intentional content. Although representationalism seems plausible with respect to ordinary perceptual states, it seems considerably less plausible for states like moods. Here the problem for representationalism arises largely because moods seem to lack intentional content altogether. In this paper, I explore several possible options for identifying the intentional content of moods and suggest that non…Read more
  •  331
    Transparency and Representationalist Theories of Consciousness
    Philosophy Compass 5 (10): 902-913. 2010.
    Over the past few decades, as philosophers of mind have begun to rethink the sharp divide that was traditionally drawn between the phenomenal character of an experience (what it’s like to have that experience) and its intentional content (what it represents), representationalist theories of consciousness have become increasingly popular. On this view, phenomenal character is reduced to intentional content. This article explores a key motivation for this theory, namely, considerations of experien…Read more
  •  524
    Panexperientialism, cognition, and the nature of experience
    PSYCHE: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Research On Consciousness 12. 2006.
    i>: This paper explores the plausibility of panexperientialism by an examination of Gregg Rosenberg.