•  251
    Belief and the problem of Ulysses and the sirens
    Philosophical Studies 77 (1): 7-37. 1995.
    This is surely a bit of Socrates' famous irony. He draws the analogy to explain how his friends should regard poetry as they regretfully banish it from the ideal state. But lovers were no more sensible then than they are now. The advice to banish poetry, undermined already by Plato's own delight and skill in drama, is perhaps undermined still further by this evocation of a 'sensible' lover who counts love so well lost. Yet Socrates' image is one of avowed rationality and prudence. The sensible l…Read more
  •  338
    Conditionalization, a new argument for
    Topoi 18 (2): 93-96. 1999.
    Probabilism in epistemology does not have to be of the Bayesian variety. The probabilist represents a person''s opinion as a probability function; the Bayesian adds that rational change of opinion must take the form of conditionalizing on new evidence. I will argue that this is the correct procedure under certain special conditions. Those special conditions are important, and instantiated for example in scientific experimentation, but hardly universal. My argument will be related to the much mal…Read more
  •  4
    A Note on Bacon's Alternative to Russell
    Philosophical Studies 18 (3): 47-48. 1967.
  •  117
  • A Problem for Relative Information Minimizers
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 32. 1981.
  •  168
    Armstrong on laws and probabilities
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65 (3). 1987.
    The question of David Armstrong's recent book, What Is a Law of Nature? would seem to have little point unless there really are laws of nature. However that may be, so much philosoFhical thinking has utilized this concept, that an inquiry of this sort was needed whether there are or not. The book begins with a devastating attack on so-called Regularity views of law, and then proceeds with an exposition of Armstrong's own answer to the question. I wish …Read more
  •  140
    Against Transcendental Empiricism
    In The Question of Hermeneutics, . pp. 309-335. 1994.
    What is empiricism? There can be no authoritative answer to any such question. A historian of philosophy can at best try to call what is common to philosophers who either identified themselves, or have traditionally been identified, as empiricists. But what has set those philosophers apart from others, and especially from those whom they criticized, may not be captured in common views or doctrines. The historian may, in trying to fix the label, rely tacitly on a view of what philosophical positi…Read more
  •  23
    A philosophical approach to foundations of science
    Foundations of Science 1 (1): 5-18. 1995.
    Foundational research focuses on the theory, but theories are to be related also to other theories, experiments, facts in their domains, data, and to their uses in applications, whether of prediction, control, or explanation. A theory is to be identified through its class of models, but not so narrowly as to disallow these roles. The language of science is to be studied separately, with special reference to the relations listed above, and to the consequent need for resources other than for theor…Read more
  •  123
    Making the abstract concrete: The role of norms and values in experimental modeling
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 46 3-10. 2014.
    Experimental modeling is the construction of theoretical models hand in hand with experimental activity. As explained in Section 1, experimental modeling starts with claims about phenomena that use abstract concepts, concepts whose conditions of realization are not yet specified; and it ends with a concrete model of the phenomenon, a model that can be tested against data. This paper argues that this process from abstract concepts to concrete models involves judgments of relevance, which are irre…Read more
  •  3
    Existence and Explanation: Essays presented in Honor of Karel Lambert (edited book)
    with W. Spohn and B. Skyrms
    Springer Verlag. 2012.
    This collection of essays is dedicated to 'Joe' Karel Lambert. The contributors are all personally affected to Joe in some way or other, but they are definitely not the only ones. Whatever excuses there are - there are some -, the editors apologize to whomever they have neglected. But even so the collection displays how influential Karel Lambert has been, personally and through his teaching and his writings. The display is in alphabetical order - with one exception: Bas van Fraassen, being about…Read more
  •  42
    Symmetry Arguments in Probability Kinematics
    with R. I. G. Hughes
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1984 851-869. 1984.
    Probability kinematics is the theory of how subjective probabilities change with time, in response to certain constraints . Rules are classified by the imposed constraints for which the rules prescribe a procedure for updating one's opinion. The first is simple conditionalization , and the second Jeffrey conditionalization . It is demonstrated by a symmetry argument that these rules are the unique admissible rules for those constraints, and moreover, that any probability kinematic rule must be e…Read more
  •  10
    Toward a Solution to the Liar Paradox
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 40 (4): 584-587. 1975.
  •  70
    Vague expectation value loss
    Philosophical Studies 127 (3). 2006.
    Vague subjective probability may be modeled by means of a set of probability functions, so that the represented opinion has only a lower and upper bound. The standard rule of conditionalization can be straightforwardly adapted to this. But this combination has difficulties which, though well known in the technical literature, have not been given sufficient attention in probabilist or Bayesian epistemology. Specifically, updating on apparently irrelevant bits of news can be destructive of one’s e…Read more
  •  5
    Reply to Belot, Elgin, and Horsten
    Philosophical Studies 150 (3): 461-472. 2010.
  •  16
    The perils of Perrin, in the hands of philosophers
    Philosophical Studies 143 (1): 5-24. 2009.
    The story of how Perrin’s experimental work established the reality of atoms and molecules has been a staple in (realist) philosophy of science writings (Wesley Salmon, Clark Glymour, Peter Achinstein, Penelope Maddy, …). I’ll argue that how this story is told distorts both what the work was and its significance, and draw morals for the understanding of how theories can be or fail to be empirically grounded.