•  75
    The status and respectability of alethic modality was always a point of contention and divergence between naturalism and empiricism. It poses no problems in principle for naturalism, since modal vocabulary is an integral part of all the candidate naturalistic base vocabularies. Fundamental physics is above all a language of laws; the special sciences distinguish between true and false counterfactual claims; and ordinary empirical talk is richly dispositional. By contrast, modality has been a stu…Read more
  •  1
    Book Reviews (review)
    with Lloyd Reinhardt
    Mind 100 (397): 149-152. 1991.
  •  81
    Wittgenstein is often thought to have challenged the view that assertion is an important theoretical category in a philosophical view of language. One of Wittgenstein’s main themes in the early sections of the Investigations is that philosophy misses important distinctions about the uses of language, distinctions hidden from us by ‘the uniform appearances of words.’ (1968, #11) As Wittgenstein goes on to say: It is like looking into the cabin of a locomotive. We see handles all looking more or l…Read more
  •  70
    The asymmetry of radiation: Reinterpreting the Wheeler-Feynman argument
    Foundations of Physics 21 (8): 959-975. 1991.
    This paper suggests a novel reinterpretation of the mathematical core of Wheeler-Feynman absorber theory, and hence a new route to the conclusion that the temporal asymmetry of classical electromagnetic radiation has the same origin as that of thermodynamics. The argument begins (Sec. 2) with a careful analysis of what the apparent asymmetry of radiation actually involves. Two major flaws in the standard version of the Wheeler-Feynman treatment of radiative asymmetry are then identified (Secs. 4…Read more
  •  441
    Toy Models for Retrocausality
    Studies in Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 39 (4): 752-761. 2008.
    A number of writers have been attracted to the idea that some of the peculiarities of quantum theory might be manifestations of 'backward' or 'retro' causality, underlying the quantum description. This idea has been explored in the literature in two main ways: firstly in a variety of explicit models of quantum systems, and secondly at a conceptual level. This note introduces a third approach, intended to complement the other two. It describes a simple toy model, which, under a natural interpreta…Read more
  •  38
    Essays in Quasi-Realism (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (4): 965-968. 1996.
  •  38
    Peter Menzies
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93 (2): 415-417. 2015.
  •  295
    Why ‘Not’?
    Mind 99 (394): 221-238. 1990.
  •  275
    Carnap, Quine and the Fate of Metaphysics
    Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy 5 (1). 1997.
    [1] Imagine a well-trained mid-century American philosopher, caught in a rare traffic jam on the New Jersey Turnpike one warm summer afternoon in the early 1950s. He dozes in his warm car ... and awakes in the same spot on a chill Fall evening in the late 1990s, remembering nothing of the intervening years. It is as if he has been asleep at the wheel for almost half a century!
  •  296
    This volume brings together fourteen major essays by one of contemporary philosophy's most challenging thinkers. Huw Price links themes from Quine, Carnap, Wittgenstein and Rorty, to craft a powerful critique of contemporary naturalistic metaphysics. He offers a new positive program for philosophy, cast from a pragmatist mould.
  •  192
    Causation, Chance, and the Rational Significance of Supernatural Evidence
    Philosophical Review 121 (4): 483-538. 2012.
    In “A Subjectivist’s Guide to Objective Chance,” David Lewis says that he is “led to wonder whether anyone but a subjectivist is in a position to understand objective chance.” The present essay aims to motivate this same Lewisean attitude, and a similar degree of modest subjectivism, with respect to objective causation. The essay begins with Newcomb problems, which turn on an apparent tension between two principles of choice: roughly, a principle sensitive to the causal features of the relevant …Read more
  •  297
    Metaphysical pluralism
    Journal of Philosophy 89 (8): 387-409. 1992.
  •  139
    The Direction of Causation: Ramsey's Ultimate Contingency
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992. 1992.
    The paper criticizes the attempt to account for the direction of causation in terms of objective statistical asymmetries, such as those of the fork asymmetry. Following Ramsey, I argue that the most plausible way to account for causal asymmetry is to regard it as "put in by hand", that is as a feature that agents project onto the world. Its temporal orientation stems from that of ourselves as agents. The crucial statistical asymmetry is an anthropocentric one, namely that we take our actions to …Read more
  •  99
    Backward causation, hidden variables and the meaning of completeness
    PRAMANA - Journal of Physics 56 199-209. 2001.
    Bell’s theorem requires the assumption that hidden variables are independent of future measurement settings. This independence assumption rests on surprisingly shaky ground. In particular, it is puzzlingly time-asymmetric. The paper begins with a summary of the case for considering hidden variable models which, in abandoning this independence assumption, allow a degree of ‘backward causation’. The remainder of the paper clarifies the physical significance of such models, in relation to the issue a…Read more
  •  233
    How to stand up for non-cognitivists
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (2): 275-292. 1996.
    Is non-cognitivism compatible with minimalism about truth? A contemporary argument claims not, and therefore that moral realists, for example, should take heart from the popularity of semantic minimalism. The same is said to apply to cognitivism about other topics—conditionals, for example—for the argument depends only on the fact that ordinary usage applies the notions of truth and falsity to utterances of the kind in question. Given this much, minimalism about truth is said to leave no room fo…Read more
  •  141
    Why is the future so different from the past? Why does the past affect the future and not the other way round? The universe began with the Big Bang - will it end with a `Big Crunch'? Now in paperback, this book presents an innovative and controversial view of time and contemporary physics. Price urges physicists, philosophers, and anyone who has ever pondered the paradoxes of time to look at the world from a fresh perspective, and throws fascinating new light on some of the great mysteries of th…Read more
  •  11
    Action Explanation and the Nature of Mind
    In Peter Slezak (ed.), Computers, Brains and Minds, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 221--251. 1989.
  •  64
    Does 'probably' modify sense?
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61 (4). 1983.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  309
    Mind and World
    Philosophical Books 38 (3): 169-181. 1994.
    How do rational minds make contact with the world? The empiricist tradition sees a gap between mind and world, and takes sensory experience, fallible as it is, to provide our only bridge across that gap. In its crudest form, for example, the traditional idea is that our minds consult an inner realm of sensory experience, which provides us with evidence about the nature of external reality. Notoriously, however, it turns out to be far from clear that there is any viable conception of experience w…Read more
  •  80
    Exchange on "Truth as convenient friction"
    with Richard Rorty
    In Mario De Caro & David Macarthur (eds.), Naturalism and Normativity, Cambridge University Press. 2010.
  •  116
    For more than a century, physics has known of a puzzling conflict between the T- asymmetry of thermodynamic phenomena and the T-symmetry of the underlying microphysics on which these phenomena depend. This paper provides a guide to the current status of this puzzle, distinguishing the central issue from various issues with which it may be confused. It is shown that there are two competing conceptions of what is needed to resolve the puzzle of the thermodynamic asymmetry, which differ with respect …Read more
  • Critical notices
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 231. 2000.
  •  96
    Newcomb problems turn on a tension between two principles of choice: roughly, a principle sensitive to the causal features of the relevant situation, and a principle sensitive only to evidential factors. Two-boxers give priority to causal beliefs, and one-boxers to evidential beliefs. A similar issue can arise when the modality in question is chance, rather than causation. In this case, the conflict is between decision rules based on credences guided solely by chances, and rules based on credence…Read more
  •  310
    Boltzmann’s Time Bomb
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 53 (1): 83-119. 2002.
    Since the late nineteenth century, physics has been puzzled by the time-asymmetry of thermodynamic phenomena in the light of the apparent T-symmetry of the underlying laws of mechanics. However, a compelling solution to this puzzle has proved elusive. In part, I argue, this can be attributed to a failure to distinguish two conceptions of the problem. According to one, the main focus of our attention is a time-asymmetric lawlike generalisation. According to the other, it is a particular fact abou…Read more