•  38
    Essays in Quasi-Realism (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (4): 965-968. 1996.
  •  38
    Peter Menzies
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93 (2): 415-417. 2015.
  •  294
    Why ‘Not’?
    Mind 99 (394): 221-238. 1990.
  •  275
    Carnap, Quine and the Fate of Metaphysics
    Electronic Journal of Analytic Philosophy 5 (1). 1997.
    [1] Imagine a well-trained mid-century American philosopher, caught in a rare traffic jam on the New Jersey Turnpike one warm summer afternoon in the early 1950s. He dozes in his warm car ... and awakes in the same spot on a chill Fall evening in the late 1990s, remembering nothing of the intervening years. It is as if he has been asleep at the wheel for almost half a century!
  •  293
    This volume brings together fourteen major essays by one of contemporary philosophy's most challenging thinkers. Huw Price links themes from Quine, Carnap, Wittgenstein and Rorty, to craft a powerful critique of contemporary naturalistic metaphysics. He offers a new positive program for philosophy, cast from a pragmatist mould.
  •  189
    Causation, Chance, and the Rational Significance of Supernatural Evidence
    Philosophical Review 121 (4): 483-538. 2012.
    In “A Subjectivist’s Guide to Objective Chance,” David Lewis says that he is “led to wonder whether anyone but a subjectivist is in a position to understand objective chance.” The present essay aims to motivate this same Lewisean attitude, and a similar degree of modest subjectivism, with respect to objective causation. The essay begins with Newcomb problems, which turn on an apparent tension between two principles of choice: roughly, a principle sensitive to the causal features of the relevant …Read more
  •  138
    The Direction of Causation: Ramsey's Ultimate Contingency
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992. 1992.
    The paper criticizes the attempt to account for the direction of causation in terms of objective statistical asymmetries, such as those of the fork asymmetry. Following Ramsey, I argue that the most plausible way to account for causal asymmetry is to regard it as "put in by hand", that is as a feature that agents project onto the world. Its temporal orientation stems from that of ourselves as agents. The crucial statistical asymmetry is an anthropocentric one, namely that we take our actions to …Read more
  •  98
    Backward causation, hidden variables and the meaning of completeness
    PRAMANA - Journal of Physics 56 199-209. 2001.
    Bell’s theorem requires the assumption that hidden variables are independent of future measurement settings. This independence assumption rests on surprisingly shaky ground. In particular, it is puzzlingly time-asymmetric. The paper begins with a summary of the case for considering hidden variable models which, in abandoning this independence assumption, allow a degree of ‘backward causation’. The remainder of the paper clarifies the physical significance of such models, in relation to the issue a…Read more
  •  296
    Metaphysical pluralism
    Journal of Philosophy 89 (8): 387-409. 1992.
  •  139
    Why is the future so different from the past? Why does the past affect the future and not the other way round? The universe began with the Big Bang - will it end with a `Big Crunch'? Now in paperback, this book presents an innovative and controversial view of time and contemporary physics. Price urges physicists, philosophers, and anyone who has ever pondered the paradoxes of time to look at the world from a fresh perspective, and throws fascinating new light on some of the great mysteries of th…Read more
  •  11
    Action Explanation and the Nature of Mind
    In Peter Slezak (ed.), Computers, Brains and Minds, Kluwer Academic Publishers. pp. 221--251. 1989.
  •  231
    How to stand up for non-cognitivists
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (2): 275-292. 1996.
    Is non-cognitivism compatible with minimalism about truth? A contemporary argument claims not, and therefore that moral realists, for example, should take heart from the popularity of semantic minimalism. The same is said to apply to cognitivism about other topics—conditionals, for example—for the argument depends only on the fact that ordinary usage applies the notions of truth and falsity to utterances of the kind in question. Given this much, minimalism about truth is said to leave no room fo…Read more
  •  306
    Mind and World
    Philosophical Books 38 (3): 169-181. 1994.
    How do rational minds make contact with the world? The empiricist tradition sees a gap between mind and world, and takes sensory experience, fallible as it is, to provide our only bridge across that gap. In its crudest form, for example, the traditional idea is that our minds consult an inner realm of sensory experience, which provides us with evidence about the nature of external reality. Notoriously, however, it turns out to be far from clear that there is any viable conception of experience w…Read more
  •  74
    Exchange on "Truth as convenient friction"
    with Richard Rorty
    In Mario De Caro & David Macarthur (eds.), Naturalism and Normativity, Cambridge University Press. 2010.
  •  63
    Does 'probably' modify sense?
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 61 (4). 1983.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  116
    For more than a century, physics has known of a puzzling conflict between the T- asymmetry of thermodynamic phenomena and the T-symmetry of the underlying microphysics on which these phenomena depend. This paper provides a guide to the current status of this puzzle, distinguishing the central issue from various issues with which it may be confused. It is shown that there are two competing conceptions of what is needed to resolve the puzzle of the thermodynamic asymmetry, which differ with respect …Read more
  • Critical notices
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 231. 2000.
  •  96
    Newcomb problems turn on a tension between two principles of choice: roughly, a principle sensitive to the causal features of the relevant situation, and a principle sensitive only to evidential factors. Two-boxers give priority to causal beliefs, and one-boxers to evidential beliefs. A similar issue can arise when the modality in question is chance, rather than causation. In this case, the conflict is between decision rules based on credences guided solely by chances, and rules based on credence…Read more
  •  309
    Boltzmann’s Time Bomb
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 53 (1): 83-119. 2002.
    Since the late nineteenth century, physics has been puzzled by the time-asymmetry of thermodynamic phenomena in the light of the apparent T-symmetry of the underlying laws of mechanics. However, a compelling solution to this puzzle has proved elusive. In part, I argue, this can be attributed to a failure to distinguish two conceptions of the problem. According to one, the main focus of our attention is a time-asymmetric lawlike generalisation. According to the other, it is a particular fact abou…Read more
  •  34
    A Realist Conception of Truth (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (1): 231-234. 2000.
  •  181
    Speech act theory is one of the more lasting products of the linguistic movement in philosophy of the mid−Twentieth century. Within philosophy itself the movement's products did not in general prove so durable. Particularly striking in this respect is the perceived fate of what was one of the most characteristic applications of the linguistic turn in philosophy, namely the view that many traditional philosophical problems are such as to yield to an understanding of the distinctive function of a …Read more
  •  234
    Agency and probabilistic causality
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 42 (2): 157-176. 1991.
    Probabilistic accounts of causality have long had trouble with ‘spurious’ evidential correlations. Such correlations are also central to the case for causal decision theory—the argument that evidential decision theory is inadequate to cope with certain sorts of decision problem. However, there are now several strong defences of the evidential theory. Here I present what I regard as the best defence, and apply it to the probabilistic approach to causality. I argue that provided a probabilistic th…Read more
  •  604
    Many areas of philosophy employ a distinction between factual and non-factual (descriptive/non-descriptive, cognitive/non-cognitive, etc) uses of language. This book examines the various ways in which this distinction is normally drawn, argues that all are unsatisfactory, and suggests that the search for a sharp distinction is misconceived. The book develops an alternative approach, based on a novel theory of the function and origins of the concept of truth. The central hypothesis is that the ma…Read more