•  10
  •  24
  •  40
    Epistemology's psychological turn
    Metaphilosophy 23 (1-2): 47-56. 1992.
  •  59
    Epistemic Internalism's Dilemma
    American Philosophical Quarterly 27 (3): 245-251. 1990.
  • Conceivability and modal knowledge
    In Tamara Horowitz & Gerald J. Massey (eds.), Thought Experiments in Science and Philosophy, Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. 1991.
    I argue for an analysis of conceivability as a form of modal knowledge: to conceive of p's being true is to know that "Possibly, p" is true.
  •  185
    Epistemology futures (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2006.
    How might epistemology build upon its past and present, so as to be better in the future? Epistemology Futures takes bold steps towards answering that question. What methods will best serve epistemology? Which phenomena and concepts deserve more attention from it? Are there approaches and assumptions that have impeded its progress until now? This volume contains provocative essays by prominent epistemologists, presenting many new ideas for possible improvements in how to do epistemology. Contrib…Read more
  •  77
    Despite the problems students often have with the theory of knowledge, it remains, necessarily, at the core of the philosophical enterprise. As experienced teachers know, teaching epistemology requires a text that is not only clear and accessible, but also capable of successfully motivating the abstract problems that arise.In Knowledge Puzzles, Stephen Hetherington presents an informal survey of epistemology based on the use of puzzles to illuminate problems of knowledge. Each topic is introduce…Read more
  •  27
    Sceptical insulation and sceptical objectivity
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 72 (4). 1994.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  34
    Stove's new irrationalism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 76 (2). 1998.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  247
    On being epistemically internal
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 51 (4): 855-871. 1991.
  •  33
    Parsons and possible objects
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 62 (3). 1984.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  32
    More on possible objects
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (1). 1988.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  67
  •  61
    Gettier and scepticism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 70 (3). 1992.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  63
    Gettieristic scepticism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (1). 1996.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  32
    Knowledge and the Gettier Problem
    Cambridge University Press. 2016.
    Edmund Gettier's 1963 verdict about what knowledge is not has become an item of philosophical orthodoxy, accepted by philosophers as a genuine epistemological result. It assures us that - contrary to what Plato and later philosophers have thought - knowledge is not merely a true belief well supported by epistemic justification. But that orthodoxy has generated the Gettier problem - epistemology's continuing struggle to understand how to accommodate Gettier's apparent result within an improved co…Read more
  •  37
    Transient global amnesia and Kantian perception
    Think 13 (38): 69-72. 2014.
    Kant's monumental Critique of Pure Reason (1781/1787) begins with his account of perception. Look around you. An experience is the result. You seem to see a chair and a person, say even perhaps of its content – are coming to you from the world, according to Kant. What else is involved?
  •  270
    Gettier problems
    Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2005.
    Gettier problems or cases are named in honor of the American philosopher Edmund Gettier, who discovered them in 1963. They function as challenges to the philosophical tradition of defining knowledge of a proposition as justified true belief in that proposition. The problems are actual or possible situations in which someone has a belief that is both true and well supported by evidence, yet which — according to almost all epistemologists — fails to be knowledge. Gettier’s original article had a d…Read more
  •  45
    Skeptical challenges and knowing actions
    Philosophical Issues 23 (1): 18-39. 2013.
  •  40
    Epistemic disaster averted
    Analysis 59 (3): 194-200. 1999.
  •  11
    Re: Brains in a Vat
    Dialectica 54 (4): 307-312. 2000.
    The hypothesis that we are brains in a vat is one which we believe to be false. Could it possibly be true, however? Metaphysical realists accept that our believing it to be false does not entail its falsity. They also accept that if –as brains in a vat –we were to say or think “We are brains in a vat”, then we would be correct. Ever the claimed foe of the metaphysical realist, though, Hilary Putnam argues that the brains‐in‐a‐vat hypothesis cannot be true, in particular that if we were brains in…Read more
  •  42
    Metaphysics and Epistemology: A Guided Anthology (edited book)
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2013.
    _Metaphysics and Epistemology: A Guided Anthology_ presents a comprehensive introductory overview of key themes, thinkers, and texts in metaphysics and epistemology. Presents a wide-ranging collection of carefully excerpted readings on metaphysics and epistemology Blends classic and contemporary works to reveal the historical development and present directions in the fields of metaphysics and epistemology Provides succinct, insightful commentary to introduce the essence of each selection at the …Read more
  •  55
    Knowing Failably
    Journal of Philosophy 96 (11): 565. 1999.
  •  43
    Technological Knowledge-That As Knowledge-How: a Comment
    Philosophy and Technology 28 (4): 567-572. 2015.
    Norström has argued that contemporary epistemological debates about the conceptual relations between knowledge-that and knowledge-how need to be supplemented by a concept of technological knowledge—with this being a further kind of knowledge. But this paper argues that Norström has not shown why technological knowledge-that is so distinctive because Norström has not shown that such knowledge cannot be reduced conceptually to a form of knowledge-how. The paper thus applies practicalism to the cas…Read more
  •  135
    Fallibilism and Knowing That One Is Not Dreaming
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 32 (1). 2002.
    Of course, if infallibilism about such knowledge is true, then it is true that one can never know that one is not dreaming. But, of course, if infallibilism is true, then there is also no special difficulty posed for one’s having knowledge in general by one’s not knowing in particular that one is not dreaming: one would know either nothing or next to nothing anyway, regardless of one’s not knowing in particular that one is not dreaming. Yet epistemologists have generally regarded the challenge o…Read more