•  19
    Book review (review)
    Philosophia 17 (1): 509-515. 1987.
  •  65
    Transcendental Idealism and the End of Philosophy
    Metaphilosophy 24 (1-2): 97-112. 1993.
    The first "Critique", Kant states inaugurates a perfectly new science'. But this transcendental philosophy', for dealing in possibilities, not actualities, does not qualify as philosophy in the traditional sense. What Kant dubs transcendental idealism' "is" however an (ontological) doctrine about things. Kant's doctrinal stand is thus inconsistent with his description of transcendental enquiry. Since transcendental idealism gets its meaning from the contrast with Cartesian realism, it follows th…Read more
  •  3
    The recent scholarly promotion of Pierre Gassendi to a key position in the formative modern period raises doubts about the portrayal of Descartes as “the father” of the post-Scholastic philosophical conceptualization. I defend the Cartesio-centric account against Thomas M. Lennon’s elliptical alternative. The defense necessitates a reassessment of the root nature of Descartes’s contribution—specifically of the interplay between philosophy and science, the latter being the crucial extraphilosophi…Read more
  •  5
    Book reviews (review)
    with Kenneth S. Friedman, Donald Gotterbarn, Bryan G. Norton, David S. Schwarz, and Walter P. Van Stigt
    Philosophia 9 (1): 75-127. 1979.
  •  59
    The structure of cartesian scepticism
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 21 (3): 343-357. 1983.
  •  53
    Descartes, Scientia and Pure Enquiry
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 19 (5): 873-886. 2011.
    In Descartes: The Project of Pure Enquiry, Bernard Williams supplies an interpretation of Descartes's Meditations in which the meditator's clean sweep of initial beliefs is justified by a stance that abrogates all practical pressures: the stance of pure enquiry. Otherwise, Williams explains, it would not be reasonable to set many of the initial beliefs aside. Nowhere, however, does Descartes assert that his approach is in this sense ?pure?. It would of course be preferable if the meditator's rej…Read more
  •  25
  •  15
    Transcendental Idealism: The Dialectical Dimension
    Dialectica 45 (1): 31-45. 1991.
    SummaryLeft wing interpreters of Kant's transcendental idealism argue that the doctrine must be excised in order to disclose the viable philosophical content of the first Critique. For right wing interpreters, this leaves a Hamlet without the prince. I chart and defend a middle path. Transcendental idealism, while essential to Kant's position, renders that position philosophically indefensible. Constant misinterpretation of the doctrine results from a failure to appreciate the inter‐theoretic re…Read more
  •  11
    Cogito
    Modern Schoolman 70 (2): 81-98. 1993.
  •  19
    Intermediate Possibility and Actuality
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 65 (1): 63-82. 1991.
  •  30
    Strawson's Hidden Realism
    Journal of Critical Analysis 5 (4): 135-145. 1975.
  •  21
    Structure and the interpretation of classical modern metaphysics
    Metaphilosophy 18 (3-4): 270-287. 1987.
  •  44
    Hume on Modes
    Hume Studies 3 (1): 32-50. 1977.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:32. HUME ON MODES As thorough a critic as Norman Kemp Smith states in his investigation of the Treatise that "Hume's treatment of... the complex ideas of modes... need not detain us." Whatever is interesting in this brief treatment, Smith suggests, rests on remarkable features of Humean doctrine, elsewhere expounded at length. This is true, I would agree, as a descriptive comment to the following degree. The category of modes is offi…Read more
  •  40
    On One Leg: The Stability of Monotheism
    Philosophy and Theology 26 (1): 187-206. 2014.
    A potential proselyte asks the great rabbi Hillel to explain the Torah to him while he stands ‘on one leg.’ Hillel responds with, essentially, the Golden Rule. This Talmudic anecdote is invariably read as critical of anyone who wants a Torah for Dummies. I offer a different interpretation. The Torah-based position, theologically speaking, rests on one principle and one principle alone, God. ‘How can an account of the creation as a whole rest on one principle only? Won’t such a structure stand un…Read more
  •  88
    A stratified bundle theory
    Synthese 42 (3). 1979.
  •  19
    In what respect, if any, is Kant a distinctively “critical” thinker? How does Kant’s “transcendentalism” differentiate his practice in metaphysics from that of the philosophers of the Cartesian tradition? How much does the success of Kant’s enterprise depend on the viability of the idea of the synthetic a priori? The issues that these questions raise came to a head for Kant in the attack on his novelty by the Leibnizean Johann August Eberhard, an attack to which Kant responded at length in the s…Read more
  •  15
    Euthyphro
    Teaching Philosophy 15 (1): 33-49. 1992.
  •  10
    Myth and Modern Philosophy. By Stephen H. Daniel (review)
    Modern Schoolman 69 (1): 62-64. 1991.
  •  25
    The Practical World
    Idealistic Studies 29 (1-2): 1-31. 1999.
    'Everything,' Kant remarks, 'gravitates ultimately towards the practical.' Judging by 'everything,' Kant is fixing on some feature of reality that he regards as invariant across times, places, and people. Judging by 'ultimately,' Kant believes that the feature yields itself up only to penetrative philosophical scrutiny. The remark is, I believe, a key to 'the basic problem confronting any reader of [Kant],' his idealism.
  •  46
    Doctrine and method in the philosophy of P. F. Strawson
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 36 (3): 364-383. 1976.
  •  4
    The "Meditations"
    Modern Schoolman 68 (4): 305-319. 1991.
  •  29
    Cartesian Substances as Modal Totalities
    Dialogue 17 (2): 320-343. 1978.
    I. Analytic interpretation of Descartes' argument for a substantial distinction between mind and body works within a framework of assumptions – which is broadly Aristotelian – concerning the character of the Cartesian categories of substance, essence, and mode. Relying on a series of texts concerning the mind/body distinction which is usually passed over by interpreters, I will develop and draw out the implications of a different – a Platonic – view of these categories.
  •  32
    Kant’s ‘Critical’ Rationalism
    Idealistic Studies 22 (2): 107-121. 1992.
    Matter, in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, plays a prototypical version of a rôle that recurs, refracted through the domestic preoccupations of each age, in metaphysical analyses of the constitution of the real. After identifying the rôle, I shall trace a developmental arc of philosophical treatment from Aristotle through the Cartesian period to Kant. The mature Kantian view of the rôle—the ‘critical’ view—is, I maintain, a reversion to the Aristotelian position. It is not however a simple reversion. I…Read more
  •  24
    The Distinction between
    Modern Schoolman 55 (4): 357-385. 1978.
  •  15
    Cartesian Certainty
    Idealistic Studies 15 (3): 219-247. 1985.
    Whence the Cartesian’s advantage over competing world investigators? Descartes’s answer is that those of his persuasion do not proceed by “resting [their] reasons on any other principle than the infinite perfections of God”. The claim’s considerable opacity does not prevent it from letting this much light filter through: only Cartesian scientists operate on the right metaphysical basis.