•  46
    Doctrine and method in the philosophy of P. F. Strawson
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 36 (3): 364-383. 1976.
  •  32
    Kant’s ‘Critical’ Rationalism
    Idealistic Studies 22 (2): 107-121. 1992.
    Matter, in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, plays a prototypical version of a rôle that recurs, refracted through the domestic preoccupations of each age, in metaphysical analyses of the constitution of the real. After identifying the rôle, I shall trace a developmental arc of philosophical treatment from Aristotle through the Cartesian period to Kant. The mature Kantian view of the rôle—the ‘critical’ view—is, I maintain, a reversion to the Aristotelian position. It is not however a simple reversion. I…Read more
  •  4
    The "Meditations"
    Modern Schoolman 68 (4): 305-319. 1991.
  •  29
    Cartesian Substances as Modal Totalities
    Dialogue 17 (2): 320-343. 1978.
    I. Analytic interpretation of Descartes' argument for a substantial distinction between mind and body works within a framework of assumptions – which is broadly Aristotelian – concerning the character of the Cartesian categories of substance, essence, and mode. Relying on a series of texts concerning the mind/body distinction which is usually passed over by interpreters, I will develop and draw out the implications of a different – a Platonic – view of these categories.
  •  1
    Intellectual intuition and cognitive assimilability
    Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 10 (3): 153-163. 1979.
  •  24
    The Distinction between
    Modern Schoolman 55 (4): 357-385. 1978.
  •  15
    Cartesian Certainty
    Idealistic Studies 15 (3): 219-247. 1985.
    Whence the Cartesian’s advantage over competing world investigators? Descartes’s answer is that those of his persuasion do not proceed by “resting [their] reasons on any other principle than the infinite perfections of God”. The claim’s considerable opacity does not prevent it from letting this much light filter through: only Cartesian scientists operate on the right metaphysical basis.
  •  13
    God incorporated
    Sophia 26 (3): 13-21. 1987.
  •  20
    Space and analogy
    Mind 84 (335): 355-373. 1975.
  •  16
    Cogitations (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 41 (2): 397-399. 1987.
    Though, in view of Descartes' challenge to the epistemological credentials of "reason" early in the Meditations, one expects him to resist the claim that the professedly invulnerable cogito argument works through the suppressed premise "Everything that thinks, exists," interpreters have been hard-pressed to convert comprendre here into pardonner. Loath to convict Descartes of confusing a psychological point about inferential process with a logical one about the conditions for validity, many are …Read more
  •  30
    Berkeley and Cognition
    Philosophy 56 (216). 1981.
    In ‘Berkeley and God’, Jonathan Bennett diagnoses Berkeley's intermittent advocacy of the proposition that physical things ‘do sometimes exist when not perceived by any human spirit’ by pinning on him the invalid argument, vitiated by the ambiguity of ‘depend’, from all ideas depend on some spirit or other, via some sensible ideas do not depend on these spirits themselves, to some ideas depend on non-finite spirits
  •  15
    Abstraction and Determinacy
    Idealistic Studies 12 (1): 14-34. 1982.
    1. The distinction between the functions of sense and intellect in cognition is first given its modern form by Kant. According to one influential commentator, Jonathan Bennett, “Kant’s breakthrough” in fact consists precisely in liberating himself from his predecessors’ misconceptions in this regard. It is true that the categorial duality of receptivity and spontaneity—of intuition and concept—is not to be found in the major classical writings prior to Kant. In its place, one encounters a relati…Read more
  • The Substance of Bundles
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 56 (1): 38. 1975.
  •  11
    Descartes: the probable and the certain
    Distributed in the U.S.A. by Humanities Press. 1986.
    System of References To keep footnotes to a minimum, references to classical sources are incorporated into the body of the narrative, normally in the ...
  •  38
    The Prussian Sphinx
    Idealistic Studies 25 (3): 255-280. 1995.
    Unhappy with a recent submission of mine, a referee for a journal specialising in the history of philosophy wagged a finger at what he or she called my ‘hermeneutical principles’. Though I am no stranger to the collegial woodshed, my initial reaction was nonetheless one of surprise. For had I then been asked about interpretive methodology I would have scoffed. The construer’s best course, I would have said, is to nose about the texts until some rough shape begins to emerge from the murk, and to …Read more
  •  10
    Cartesian Uncertainty
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 27 (1): 101-124. 1986.
    For placing the contrast of certainty and uncertainty at the philosophical center, Descartes is charged with Michael Dummett with mistakenly subordinating the study of language and meaning to epistemology. But Dummett's knowledge-theoretic reading of the certainty/uncertainty duality is as erroneous as the tradition it inherits is long. The Cartesian demand for certainty and critique of uncertainty in mature writings like the Meditations has a definite semantic character. Cartesian uncertainty, …Read more
  •  64
    Invitation to a beheading: The career of philosophy
    Philosophia 28 (1-4): 39-66. 2001.
    Registrants for the academic study of philosophy, expecting an encounter with special cognitive products, regal truths, are soon enough disabused. Philosophy, its supposedly special access to the structure of things exploded, is relegated to sundry tasks of intellectual hygiene. I track down the source of the unrealistic view, anatomising what has a strong claim to be regarded as the regal enterprise’s inau¬gural reasoning—in Plato. When professionals consider the successor activity that is call…Read more
  •  11
    RÉSUMÉ: La Bible éclaire la distinction kantienne entre les apparences et les choses en soi. Les deux récits bibliques de la création, dans Genèse 1 et 2, offrent différentes analyses ontologiques, et seule la deuxième est, comme les apparences de Kant, relative à la condition humaine. Mais, tandis que l’autre région dont Kant parle est sans caractérisation positive, la Bible décrit amplement le monde tel qu’il est avant l’avènement des hommes et des femmes. La Bible traite de ce domaine du poin…Read more
  •  16
    Cartesian Probability and Cognitive Structure
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 36 (4). 1982.
  •  19
    How Philosophers See 'Red'
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 4 (1): 43-64. 1977.
    To what extent is conceptual analysis under strict semantic control? In an effort to show that conceptual structure transcends the linguistic dimension proper, the tensions within, and between, several current treatments of the concept red are revealed and explored. It is argued that certain extra-semantic factors — factors, broadly speaking, which concern the manner in which a concept applier interacts with the world as an extralinguistic agent - provide a backdrop against which conceptual anal…Read more
  • Conceptuality: An Essay in Retrieval
    Société Française de Philosophie, Bulletin 70 (4): 383. 1979.
  •  67
    Book reviews (review)
    with Zeno Vendler, Gary Jason, George N. Schlesinger, Roberto Torretti, Bowman L. Clarke, Richard T. De George, Avner Cohen, Tecla Mazzarese, A. Modal Logician, and J. Gellman
    Philosophia 17 (2): 211-216. 1987.
  •  29
    Progress and regress in philosophy
    Philosophia 5 (4): 529-540. 1975.
  •  96
    Berkeley's anti‐abstractionism
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 2 (1). 1994.
  •  50
  •  16
    Error Theory: Logic, Rhetoric, and Philosophy
    Journal of Speculative Philosophy 4 (1). 1990.