•  15
    Transcendental Idealism: The Dialectical Dimension
    Dialectica 45 (1): 31-45. 1991.
    SummaryLeft wing interpreters of Kant's transcendental idealism argue that the doctrine must be excised in order to disclose the viable philosophical content of the first Critique. For right wing interpreters, this leaves a Hamlet without the prince. I chart and defend a middle path. Transcendental idealism, while essential to Kant's position, renders that position philosophically indefensible. Constant misinterpretation of the doctrine results from a failure to appreciate the inter‐theoretic re…Read more
  •  11
    Cogito
    Modern Schoolman 70 (2): 81-98. 1993.
  •  21
    Structure and the interpretation of classical modern metaphysics
    Metaphilosophy 18 (3-4): 270-287. 1987.
  •  43
    Hume on Modes
    Hume Studies 3 (1): 32-50. 1977.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:32. HUME ON MODES As thorough a critic as Norman Kemp Smith states in his investigation of the Treatise that "Hume's treatment of... the complex ideas of modes... need not detain us." Whatever is interesting in this brief treatment, Smith suggests, rests on remarkable features of Humean doctrine, elsewhere expounded at length. This is true, I would agree, as a descriptive comment to the following degree. The category of modes is offi…Read more
  •  30
    Strawson's Hidden Realism
    Journal of Critical Analysis 5 (4): 135-145. 1975.
  •  15
    Euthyphro
    Teaching Philosophy 15 (1): 33-49. 1992.
  •  41
    On One Leg: The Stability of Monotheism
    Philosophy and Theology 26 (1): 187-206. 2014.
    A potential proselyte asks the great rabbi Hillel to explain the Torah to him while he stands ‘on one leg.’ Hillel responds with, essentially, the Golden Rule. This Talmudic anecdote is invariably read as critical of anyone who wants a Torah for Dummies. I offer a different interpretation. The Torah-based position, theologically speaking, rests on one principle and one principle alone, God. ‘How can an account of the creation as a whole rest on one principle only? Won’t such a structure stand un…Read more
  •  88
    A stratified bundle theory
    Synthese 42 (3). 1979.
  •  70
    In what respect, if any, is Kant a distinctively “critical” thinker? How does Kant’s “transcendentalism” differentiate his practice in metaphysics from that of the philosophers of the Cartesian tradition? How much does the success of Kant’s enterprise depend on the viability of the idea of the synthetic a priori? The issues that these questions raise came to a head for Kant in the attack on his novelty by the Leibnizean Johann August Eberhard, an attack to which Kant responded at length in the s…Read more
  •  46
    Doctrine and method in the philosophy of P. F. Strawson
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 36 (3): 364-383. 1976.
  •  22
    Myth and Modern Philosophy. By Stephen H. Daniel (review)
    Modern Schoolman 69 (1): 62-64. 1991.
  •  25
    The Practical World
    Idealistic Studies 29 (1-2): 1-31. 1999.
    'Everything,' Kant remarks, 'gravitates ultimately towards the practical.' Judging by 'everything,' Kant is fixing on some feature of reality that he regards as invariant across times, places, and people. Judging by 'ultimately,' Kant believes that the feature yields itself up only to penetrative philosophical scrutiny. The remark is, I believe, a key to 'the basic problem confronting any reader of [Kant],' his idealism.
  •  32
    Kant’s ‘Critical’ Rationalism
    Idealistic Studies 22 (2): 107-121. 1992.
    Matter, in Aristotle’s Metaphysics, plays a prototypical version of a rôle that recurs, refracted through the domestic preoccupations of each age, in metaphysical analyses of the constitution of the real. After identifying the rôle, I shall trace a developmental arc of philosophical treatment from Aristotle through the Cartesian period to Kant. The mature Kantian view of the rôle—the ‘critical’ view—is, I maintain, a reversion to the Aristotelian position. It is not however a simple reversion. I…Read more
  •  22
    The "Meditations"
    Modern Schoolman 68 (4): 305-319. 1991.
  •  29
    Cartesian Substances as Modal Totalities
    Dialogue 17 (2): 320-343. 1978.
    I. Analytic interpretation of Descartes' argument for a substantial distinction between mind and body works within a framework of assumptions – which is broadly Aristotelian – concerning the character of the Cartesian categories of substance, essence, and mode. Relying on a series of texts concerning the mind/body distinction which is usually passed over by interpreters, I will develop and draw out the implications of a different – a Platonic – view of these categories.
  •  1
    Intellectual intuition and cognitive assimilability
    Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 10 (3): 153-163. 1979.
  •  24
    The Distinction between
    Modern Schoolman 55 (4): 357-385. 1978.
  •  15
    Cartesian Certainty
    Idealistic Studies 15 (3): 219-247. 1985.
    Whence the Cartesian’s advantage over competing world investigators? Descartes’s answer is that those of his persuasion do not proceed by “resting [their] reasons on any other principle than the infinite perfections of God”. The claim’s considerable opacity does not prevent it from letting this much light filter through: only Cartesian scientists operate on the right metaphysical basis.
  •  13
    God incorporated
    Sophia 26 (3): 13-21. 1987.
  •  20
    Space and analogy
    Mind 84 (335): 355-373. 1975.
  •  16
    Cogitations (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 41 (2): 397-399. 1987.
    Though, in view of Descartes' challenge to the epistemological credentials of "reason" early in the Meditations, one expects him to resist the claim that the professedly invulnerable cogito argument works through the suppressed premise "Everything that thinks, exists," interpreters have been hard-pressed to convert comprendre here into pardonner. Loath to convict Descartes of confusing a psychological point about inferential process with a logical one about the conditions for validity, many are …Read more
  •  30
    Berkeley and Cognition
    Philosophy 56 (216). 1981.
    In ‘Berkeley and God’, Jonathan Bennett diagnoses Berkeley's intermittent advocacy of the proposition that physical things ‘do sometimes exist when not perceived by any human spirit’ by pinning on him the invalid argument, vitiated by the ambiguity of ‘depend’, from all ideas depend on some spirit or other, via some sensible ideas do not depend on these spirits themselves, to some ideas depend on non-finite spirits
  •  11
    Descartes: the probable and the certain
    Distributed in the U.S.A. by Humanities Press. 1986.
    System of References To keep footnotes to a minimum, references to classical sources are incorporated into the body of the narrative, normally in the ...
  •  43
    Abstraction and Determinacy
    Idealistic Studies 12 (1): 14-34. 1982.
    1. The distinction between the functions of sense and intellect in cognition is first given its modern form by Kant. According to one influential commentator, Jonathan Bennett, “Kant’s breakthrough” in fact consists precisely in liberating himself from his predecessors’ misconceptions in this regard. It is true that the categorial duality of receptivity and spontaneity—of intuition and concept—is not to be found in the major classical writings prior to Kant. In its place, one encounters a relati…Read more
  • The Substance of Bundles
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 56 (1): 38. 1975.
  •  38
    The Prussian Sphinx
    Idealistic Studies 25 (3): 255-280. 1995.
    Unhappy with a recent submission of mine, a referee for a journal specialising in the history of philosophy wagged a finger at what he or she called my ‘hermeneutical principles’. Though I am no stranger to the collegial woodshed, my initial reaction was nonetheless one of surprise. For had I then been asked about interpretive methodology I would have scoffed. The construer’s best course, I would have said, is to nose about the texts until some rough shape begins to emerge from the murk, and to …Read more
  •  10
    Cartesian Uncertainty
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 27 (1): 101-124. 1986.
    For placing the contrast of certainty and uncertainty at the philosophical center, Descartes is charged with Michael Dummett with mistakenly subordinating the study of language and meaning to epistemology. But Dummett's knowledge-theoretic reading of the certainty/uncertainty duality is as erroneous as the tradition it inherits is long. The Cartesian demand for certainty and critique of uncertainty in mature writings like the Meditations has a definite semantic character. Cartesian uncertainty, …Read more