•  177
    Underdetermination, holism and the theory/data distinction
    Philosophical Quarterly 52 (208): 303-319. 2002.
    I examine the argument that scientific theories are typically 'underdetermined' by the data, an argument which has often been used to combat scientific realism. I deal with two objections to the underdetermination argument: (i) that the argument conflicts with the holistic nature of confirmation, and (ii) that the argument rests on an untenable theory/data dualism. I discuss possible responses to both objections, and argue that in both cases the proponent of underdetermination can respond in way…Read more
  •  64
    The concept of group heritability
    Biology and Philosophy 18 (3): 445-461. 2003.
    This paper investigates the role of the concept of group heritability in group selection theory, in relation to the well-known distinction between type 1 and type 2 group selection (GS1 and GS2). I argue that group heritability is required for the operation of GS1 but not GS2, despite what a number of authors have claimed. I offer a numerical example of the evolution of altruism in a multi-group population which demonstrates that a group heritability coefficient of zero is perfectly compatible w…Read more
  •  36
    How to be a selective Quinean
    Dialectica 56 (1). 2002.
    This paper examines whether one can accept Quine's critique of the analytic/synthetic distinction while rejecting his indeterminacy of translation thesis. I argue that this is possible, appearances to the contrary notwithstanding. Holding that linguistic synonymy is a well‐defined relation, and that translation is thus a determinate matter, does not commit one to the existence of an analytic‐synthetic distinction capable of playing the explanatory role that the traditional distinction was suppos…Read more
  •  87
    Replies to my critics
    Biology and Philosophy 25 (3): 425-431. 2010.
    This paper contains replies to the reviews of my book by Steven Downes, Massimo Pigliucci and Deborah Shelton & Rick Michod.
  •  38
    Emergent group traits, reproduction, and levels of selection
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 37 (3): 268-269. 2014.
  •  71
    Philosophical theories of probability (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 53 (1): 151-156. 2002.
  •  152
    Modeling in biology and economics
    Biology and Philosophy 26 (5): 613-615. 2011.
    Much of biological and economic theorizing takes place by modeling, the indirect study of real-world phenomena by the construction and examination of models. Books and articles about biological and economic theory are often books and articles about models, many of which are highly idealized and chosen for their explanatory power and analytical convenience rather than for their fit with known data sets. Philosophers of science have recognized these facts and have developed literatures about the n…Read more
  •  62
    Does the concept of “clade selection” make sense?
    Philosophy of Science 70 (4): 739-751. 2003.
    The idea that clades might be units of selection, defended by a number of biologists and philosophers of biology, is critically examined. I argue that only entities which reproduce, i.e. leave offspring, can be units of selection, and that a necessary condition of reproduction is that the offspring entity be able, in principle, to outlive its parental entity. Given that clades are monophlyetic by definition, it follows that clades do not reproduce, so it makes no sense to talk about a clade's fi…Read more
  •  89
    Optimal Choice in the Face of Risk: Decision Theory Meets Evolution
    Philosophy of Science 78 (1): 83-104. 2011.
    The problem of how to make optimal choices in the face of risk arises in both economics/decision theory and also evolutionary biology; in the former, ‘optimal’ means utility maximizing, while in the latter it means fitness maximizing. This article explores the links, thematic and formal, between the economic and evolutionary theories of optimal choice in risky situations, with particular reference to the relationship between utility and fitness. It is argued that the link is strongest between ev…Read more
  •  15
    What did Hume Really Show about Induction&quest
    Philosophical Quarterly 51 (204): 307-327. 2001.
  •  221
    Bayesianism and the Traditional Problem of Induction
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 5 (2): 181-194. 2005.
    Many philosophers argue that Bayesian epistemology cannot help us with the traditional Humean problem of induction. I argue that this view is partially but not wholly correct. It is true that Bayesianism does not solve Hume’s problem, in the way that the classical and logical theories of probability aimed to do. However I argue that in one important respect, Hume’s sceptical challenge cannot simply be transposed to a probabilistic context, where beliefs come in degrees, rather than being a yes/n…Read more
  •  61
    Bowles and Gintis argue that recent work in behavioural economics shows that humans have other-regarding preferences, i.e., are not purely self-interested. They seek to explain how these preferences may have evolved using a multi-level version of gene-culture coevolutionary theory. In this review essay I critically examine their main arguments
  •  147
    Fodor on cognition, modularity, and adaptationism
    Philosophy of Science 70 (1): 68-88. 2003.
    This paper critically examines Jerry Fodor's latest attacks on evolutionary psychology. Contra Leda Cosmides and John Tooby, Fodor argues (i) there is no reason to think that human cognition is a Darwinian adaptation in the first place, and (ii) there is no valid inference from adaptationism about the mind to massive modularity. However, Fodor maintains (iii) that there is a valid inference in the converse direction, from modularity to adaptationism, but (iv) that the language module is an excep…Read more
  •  83
    Review. Genetics and reductionism. S Sarkar
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (1): 181-185. 2000.
  •  161
    Evolution and the levels of selection
    Oxford University Press. 2006.
    Does natural selection act primarily on individual organisms, on groups, on genes, or on whole species? The question of levels of selection - on which biologists and philosophers have long disagreed - is central to evolutionary theory and to the philosophy of biology. Samir Okasha's comprehensive analysis gives a clear account of the philosophical issues at stake in the current debate.
  •  154
    Probabilistic Induction and Hume’s Problem: Reply to Lange
    Philosophical Quarterly 53 (212). 2003.
    Marc Lange has criticized my assertion that relative to a Bayesian conception of inductive reasoning, Hume's argument for inductive scepticism cannot be run. I reply that the way in which Lange suggests one should run the Humean argument in a Bayesian framework ignores the fact that in Bayesian models of learning from experience, the domain of an agent's probability measure is exogenously determined. I also show that Lange is incorrect to equate probability distributions which 'support inductive…Read more
  •  144
    Why won't the group selection controversy go away?
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 52 (1): 25-50. 2001.
    The group selection controversy is about whether natural selection ever operates at the level of groups, rather than at the level of individual organisms. Traditionally, group selection has been invoked to explain the existence of altruistic behaviour in nature. However, most contemporary evolutionary biologists are highly sceptical of the hypothesis of group selection, which they regard as biologically implausible and not needed to explain the evolution of altruism anyway. But in their recent b…Read more