•  64
    Function and concatenation
    In Georg Peter & Gerhard Preyer (eds.), Logical Form and Language, Oxford University Press. pp. 91--117. 2002.
    Paul M. Pietroski, University of Maryland For any sentence of a natural language, we can ask the following questions: what is its meaning; what is its syntactic structure; and how is its meaning related to its syntactic structure? Attending to these questions, as they apply to sentences that provide evidence for Davidsonian event analyses, suggests that we reconsider some traditional views about how the syntax of a natural sentence is related to its meaning.
  •  58
    Framing Event Variables
    Erkenntnis 80 (1): 31-60. 2015.
    Davidsonian analyses of action reports like ‘Alvin chased Theodore around a tree’ are often viewed as supporting the hypothesis that sentences of a human language H have truth conditions that can be specified by a Tarski-style theory of truth for H. But in my view, simple cases of adverbial modification add to the reasons for rejecting this hypothesis, even though Davidson rightly diagnosed many implications involving adverbs as cases of conjunct-reduction in the scope of an existential quantifi…Read more
  •  57
    A narrow path from meanings to contents
    Philosophical Studies 178 (9): 3027-3035. 2020.
    In this comment on Yli-Vakkuri and Hawthorne's illuminating book, Narrow Content, I address some issues related to externalist conceptions of linguistic meaning.
  •  54
    Euthyphro and the semantic
    Mind and Language 15 (2-3): 341-349. 2000.
  •  54
    Quantification and second order monadicity
    Philosophical Perspectives 17 (1). 2003.
  •  53
    Interpreting concatenation and concatenates
    Philosophical Issues 16 (1). 2006.
    This paper presents a slightly modified version of the compositional semantics proposed in Events and Semantic Architecture (OUP 2005). Some readers may find this shorter version, which ignores issues about vagueness and causal constructions, easier to digest. The emphasis is on the treatments of plurality and quantification, and I assume at least some familiarity with more standard approaches.
  •  50
    A “should” too many
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 17 (1): 26-27. 1994.
  •  48
    Character before content
    In Judith Jarvis Thomson (ed.), Content and Modality: Themes From the Philosophy of Robert Stalnaker, Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 34--60. 2006.
    Speakers can use sentences to make assertions. Theorists who reflect on this truism often say that sentences have linguistic meanings, and that assertions have propositional contents. But how are meanings related to contents? Are meanings less dependent on the environment? Are contents more independent of language? These are large questions, which must be understood partly in terms of the phenomena that lead theorists to use words like ‘meaning’ and ‘content’, sometimes in nonstandard ways. Oppo…Read more
  •  45
    Minimal Semantic Instructions
    In Boeckx Cedric (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Minimalism, Oxford University Press. pp. 472-498. 2011.
    Chomsky’s (1995, 2000a) Minimalist Program (MP) invites a perspective on semantics that is distinctive and attractive. In section one, I discuss a general idea that many theorists should find congenial: the spoken or signed languages that human children naturally acquire and use— henceforth, human languages—are biologically implemented procedures that generate expressions, whose meanings are recursively combinable instructions to build concepts that reflect a minimal interface between the Human …Read more
  •  45
    LOT 2: The Language of Thought Revisited (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 107 (12): 653-658. 2010.
  •  43
  •  43
    8 Innate ideas
    with Stephen Crain
    In James A. McGilvray (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Chomsky, Cambridge University Press. pp. 164. 2005.
  •  43
    Knowledge by ignoring
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (5): 781-781. 1999.
    Some cases of implicit knowledge involve representations of (implicitly) known propositions, but this is not the only important type of implicit knowledge. Chomskian linguistics suggests another model of how humans can know more than is accessible to consciousness. Innate capacities to focus on a small range of possibilities, thereby ignoring many others, need not be grounded by inner representations of any possibilities ignored. This model may apply to many domains where human cognition “fills …Read more
  •  38
    The mental representation of universal quantifiers
    with Tyler Knowlton, Justin Halberda, and Jeffrey Lidz
    Linguistics and Philosophy 45 (4): 911-941. 2022.
    A sentence like every circle is blue might be understood in terms of individuals and their properties or in terms of a relation between groups. Relatedly, theorists can specify the contents of universally quantified sentences in first-order or second-order terms. We offer new evidence that this logical first-order vs. second-order distinction corresponds to a psychologically robust individual vs. group distinction that has behavioral repercussions. Participants were shown displays of dots and as…Read more
  •  38
    Responses to comments on Conjoining meanings
    Mind and Language 35 (2): 266-273. 2020.
    After some brief introductory remarks, I respond to the three commentaries on Conjoining meanings that appear in this issue.
  •  35
    Natural number concepts: No derivation without formalization
    with Jeffrey Lidz
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (6): 666-667. 2008.
    The conceptual building blocks suggested by developmental psychologists may yet play a role in how the human learner arrives at an understanding of natural number. The proposal of Rips et al. faces a challenge, yet to be met, faced by all developmental proposals: to describe the logical space in which learners ever acquire new concepts
  •  35
    Lot 2 (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 107 (12): 653-658. 2010.
  •  33
    On Explaining That
    Journal of Philosophy 97 (12): 655. 2000.
  •  33
    Replies to Critics
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 105 (3): 752-764. 2022.
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, EarlyView.
  •  33
    Fostering Liars
    Topoi 40 (1): 5-25. 2020.
    Davidson conjectured that suitably formulated Tarski-style theories of truth can “do duty” as theories of meaning for the spoken languages that humans naturally acquire. But this conjecture faces a pair of old objections that are, in my view, fatal when combined. Foster noted that given any theory of the sort Davidson envisioned, for a language L, there will be many equally true theories whose theorems pair endlessly many sentences of L with very different specifications of whether or not those …Read more
  •  29
    Psycholinguistic evidence for restricted quantification
    with Tyler Knowlton, Alexander Williams, Justin Halberda, and Jeffrey Lidz
    Natural Language Semantics 31 (2): 219-251. 2023.
    Quantificational determiners are often said to be devices for expressing relations. For example, the meaning of _every_ is standardly described as the inclusion relation, with a sentence like _every frog is green_ meaning roughly that the green things include the frogs. Here, we consider an older, non-relational alternative: determiners are tools for creating restricted quantifiers. On this view, determiners specify how many elements of a restricted domain (e.g., the frogs) satisfy a given condi…Read more
  •  29
    Précis of Conjoining Meanings
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 20 (3): 271-282. 2020.
    In Conjoining Meanings, I argue that meanings are composable instructions for how to build concepts of a special kind. In this summary of the main line of argument, I stress that proposals about what linguistic meanings are should make room for the phenomenon of lexical polysemy. On my internalist proposal, a single lexical item can be used to access various concepts on different occasions of use. And if lexical items are often “conceptually equivocal” in this way, then some familiar arguments f…Read more
  •  28
    Paul M. Pietroski presents an ambitious new account of human languages as generative procedures that respect substantive constraints. He argues that meanings are neither concepts nor extensions, and sentences do not have truth conditions; meanings are composable instructions for how to access and assemble concepts of a special sort.
  •  26
    Precis of Conjoining Meanings
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 105 (3): 730-734. 2023.
  •  24
    Describing I-junction
    ProtoSociology 31 121-137. 2014.
    The meaning of a noun phrase like ‘brown cow’, or ‘cow that ate grass’, is somehow conjunctive. But conjunctive in what sense? Are the meanings of other phrases—e.g, ‘ate quickly’, ‘ate grass’, and ‘at noon’—similarly conjunctive? I suggest a possible answer, in the context of a broader conception of natural language semantics. But my main aim is to highlight some underdiscussed questions and some implications of our ignorance.
  •  21
    Logical Form and LF
    In Ernest Lepore & Barry C. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language, Oxford University Press. pp. 822--841. 2006.
    We can use sentences to present arguments, some of which are valid. This suggests that premises and conclusions, like sentences, have structure. This in turn raises questions about how logical structure is related to grammar, and how grammatical structure is related to thought and truth.
  •  19
    Quantification and Second-Order Quantification
    Philosophical Perspectives 17 (1): 259--298. 2003.