• Does every sentence like this exhibit a scope ambiguity
    with Norbert Hornstein
    In Wolfram Hinzen & Hans Rott (eds.), Belief and Meaning: Essays at the Interface, Deutsche Bibliothek Der Wissenschaften. pp. 43--72. 2002.
  •  5
    Meaning before truth
    In Gerhard Preyer & Georg Peter (eds.), Contextualism in Philosophy: Knowledge, Meaning, and Truth, Oxford University Press. 2005.
  •  43
    8 Innate ideas
    with Stephen Crain
    In James A. McGilvray (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Chomsky, Cambridge University Press. pp. 164. 2005.
  •  409
    When Other Things Aren’t Equal: Saving Ceteris Paribus Laws from Vacuity
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 46 (1): 81-110. 1995.
    A common view is that ceteris paribus clauses render lawlike statements vacuous, unless such clauses can be explicitly reformulated as antecedents of ?real? laws that face no counterinstances. But such reformulations are rare; and they are not, we argue, to be expected in general. So we defend an alternative sufficient condition for the non-vacuity of ceteris paribus laws: roughly, any counterinstance of the law must be independently explicable, in a sense we make explicit. Ceteris paribus laws …Read more
  •  54
    Euthyphro and the semantic
    Mind and Language 15 (2-3): 341-349. 2000.
  •  107
    Actions, adjuncts, and agency
    Mind 107 (425): 73-111. 1998.
    The event analysis of action sentences seems to be at odds with plausible (Davidsonian) views about how to count actions. If Booth pulled a certain trigger, and thereby shot Lincoln, there is good reason for identifying Booths' action of pulling the trigger with his action of shooting Lincoln; but given truth conditions of certain sentences involving adjuncts, the event analysis requires that the pulling and the shooting be distinct events. So I propose that event sortals like 'shooting' and 'pu…Read more
  •  33
    On Explaining That
    Journal of Philosophy 97 (12): 655. 2000.
  •  423
    Nature, nurture, and universal grammar
    Linguistics and Philosophy 24 (2): 139-186. 2001.
    In just a few years, children achieve a stable state of linguistic competence, making them effectively adults with respect to: understanding novel sentences, discerning relations of paraphrase and entailment, acceptability judgments, etc. One familiar account of the language acquisition process treats it as an induction problem of the sort that arises in any domain where the knowledge achieved is logically underdetermined by experience. This view highlights the cues that are available in the inp…Read more
  •  21
    Logical Form and LF
    In Ernest Lepore & Barry C. Smith (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language, Oxford University Press. pp. 822--841. 2006.
    We can use sentences to present arguments, some of which are valid. This suggests that premises and conclusions, like sentences, have structure. This in turn raises questions about how logical structure is related to grammar, and how grammatical structure is related to thought and truth.
  •  58
    Framing Event Variables
    Erkenntnis 80 (1): 31-60. 2015.
    Davidsonian analyses of action reports like ‘Alvin chased Theodore around a tree’ are often viewed as supporting the hypothesis that sentences of a human language H have truth conditions that can be specified by a Tarski-style theory of truth for H. But in my view, simple cases of adverbial modification add to the reasons for rejecting this hypothesis, even though Davidson rightly diagnosed many implications involving adverbs as cases of conjunct-reduction in the scope of an existential quantifi…Read more
  •  125
    The meaning of 'most': Semantics, numerosity and psychology
    with Jeffrey Lidz, Tim Hunter, and Justin Halberda
    Mind and Language 24 (5): 554-585. 2009.
    The meaning of 'most' can be described in many ways. We offer a framework for distinguishing semantic descriptions, interpreted as psychological hypotheses that go beyond claims about sentential truth conditions, and an experiment that tells against an attractive idea: 'most' is understood in terms of one-to-one correspondence. Adults evaluated 'Most of the dots are yellow', as true or false, on many trials in which yellow dots and blue dots were displayed for 200 ms. Displays manipulated the ea…Read more
  •  48
    Character before content
    In Judith Jarvis Thomson (ed.), Content and Modality: Themes From the Philosophy of Robert Stalnaker, Oxford: Clarendon Press. pp. 34--60. 2006.
    Speakers can use sentences to make assertions. Theorists who reflect on this truism often say that sentences have linguistic meanings, and that assertions have propositional contents. But how are meanings related to contents? Are meanings less dependent on the environment? Are contents more independent of language? These are large questions, which must be understood partly in terms of the phenomena that lead theorists to use words like ‘meaning’ and ‘content’, sometimes in nonstandard ways. Oppo…Read more
  •  54
    Quantification and second order monadicity
    Philosophical Perspectives 17 (1). 2003.
  •  89
    Interface transparency and the psychosemantics of most
    with Jeffrey Lidz, Tim Hunter, and Justin Halberda
    Natural Language Semantics 19 (3): 227-256. 2011.
    This paper proposes an Interface Transparency Thesis concerning how linguistic meanings are related to the cognitive systems that are used to evaluate sentences for truth/falsity: a declarative sentence S is semantically associated with a canonical procedure for determining whether S is true; while this procedure need not be used as a verification strategy, competent speakers are biased towards strategies that directly reflect canonical specifications of truth conditions. Evidence in favor of th…Read more
  •  45
    Minimal Semantic Instructions
    In Boeckx Cedric (ed.), Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Minimalism, Oxford University Press. pp. 472-498. 2011.
    Chomsky’s (1995, 2000a) Minimalist Program (MP) invites a perspective on semantics that is distinctive and attractive. In section one, I discuss a general idea that many theorists should find congenial: the spoken or signed languages that human children naturally acquire and use— henceforth, human languages—are biologically implemented procedures that generate expressions, whose meanings are recursively combinable instructions to build concepts that reflect a minimal interface between the Human …Read more
  •  330
    Poverty of the Stimulus Revisited
    with Robert C. Berwick, Beracah Yankama, and Noam Chomsky
    Cognitive Science 35 (7): 1207-1242. 2011.
    A central goal of modern generative grammar has been to discover invariant properties of human languages that reflect “the innate schematism of mind that is applied to the data of experience” and that “might reasonably be attributed to the organism itself as its contribution to the task of the acquisition of knowledge” (Chomsky, 1971). Candidates for such invariances include the structure dependence of grammatical rules, and in particular, certain constraints on question formation. Various “pove…Read more
  •  43
    Knowledge by ignoring
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (5): 781-781. 1999.
    Some cases of implicit knowledge involve representations of (implicitly) known propositions, but this is not the only important type of implicit knowledge. Chomskian linguistics suggests another model of how humans can know more than is accessible to consciousness. Innate capacities to focus on a small range of possibilities, thereby ignoring many others, need not be grounded by inner representations of any possibilities ignored. This model may apply to many domains where human cognition “fills …Read more
  •  120
    Experiencing the facts (critical notice of McDowell)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 26 (4): 613-36. 1996.
    The general topic of "Mind and World", the written version of John McDowell's 1991 John Locke Lectures, is how `concepts mediate the relation between minds and the world'. And one of the main aims is `to suggest that Kant should still have a central place in our discussion of the way thought bears on reality' (1).1 In particular, McDowell urges us to adopt a thesis that he finds in Kant, or perhaps in Strawson's Kant: the content of experience is conceptualized; _what_ we experience is always th…Read more
  •  95
    Small verbs, complex events: Analyticity without synonymy
    In Louise M. Antony (ed.), Chomsky and His Critics, Blackwell. pp. 179--214. 2003.
    This chapter contains section titled: Hidden Tautologies Minimal Syntax.
  •  265
    A Defense of Derangement
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24 (1). 1994.
    In a recent paper, Bar-On and Risjord (henceforth, 'B&R') contend that Davidson provides no 1 good argument for his (in)famous claim that "there is no such thing as a language." And according to B&R, if Davidson had established his "no language" thesis, he would thereby have provided a decisive reason for abandoning the project he has long advocated--viz., that of trying to provide theories of meaning for natural languages by providing recursive theories of truth for such languages. For he would…Read more
  •  174
    Why language acquisition is a snap
    with Stephen Crain
    Linguistic Review. 2002.
    Nativists inspired by Chomsky are apt to provide arguments with the following general form: languages exhibit interesting generalizations that are not suggested by casual (or even intensive) examination of what people actually say; correspondingly, adults (i.e., just about anyone above the age of four) know much more about language than they could plausibly have learned on the basis of their experience; so absent an alternative account of the relevant generalizations and speakers' (tacit) knowle…Read more
  •  45
    LOT 2: The Language of Thought Revisited (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 107 (12): 653-658. 2010.
  •  53
    Interpreting concatenation and concatenates
    Philosophical Issues 16 (1). 2006.
    This paper presents a slightly modified version of the compositional semantics proposed in Events and Semantic Architecture (OUP 2005). Some readers may find this shorter version, which ignores issues about vagueness and causal constructions, easier to digest. The emphasis is on the treatments of plurality and quantification, and I assume at least some familiarity with more standard approaches.
  •  87
    Think of the children
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 86 (4). 2008.
    Often, the deepest disagreements are about starting points, and which considerations are relevant.
  •  199
    I argue that linguistic meanings are instructions to build monadic concepts that lie between lexicalizable concepts and truth-evaluable judgments. In acquiring words, humans use concepts of various adicities to introduce concepts that can be fetched and systematically combined via certain conjunctive operations, which require monadic inputs. These concepts do not have Tarskian satisfaction conditions. But they provide bases for refinements and elaborations that can yield truth-evaluable judgment…Read more
  •  19
    Quantification and Second-Order Quantification
    Philosophical Perspectives 17 (1): 259--298. 2003.
  •  174
    Mental causation for dualists
    Mind and Language 9 (3): 336-366. 1994.
    The philosophical problem of mental causation concerns a clash between commonsense and scientific views about the causation of human behaviour. On the one hand, commonsense suggests that our actions are caused by our mental states—our thoughts, intentions, beliefs and so on. On the other hand, neuroscience assumes that all bodily movements are caused by neurochemical events. It is implausible to suppose that our actions are causally overdetermined in the same way that the ringing of a bell may b…Read more
  •  35
    Natural number concepts: No derivation without formalization
    with Jeffrey Lidz
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 31 (6): 666-667. 2008.
    The conceptual building blocks suggested by developmental psychologists may yet play a role in how the human learner arrives at an understanding of natural number. The proposal of Rips et al. faces a challenge, yet to be met, faced by all developmental proposals: to describe the logical space in which learners ever acquire new concepts