• Partikularistisk konsekventialism
    Filosofisk Tidskrift 3. 2004.
  •  103
    Intrinsicalism and conditionalism about final value
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 7 (1): 31-52. 2004.
    The paper distinguishes between two rival views about the nature of final value (i.e. the value something has for its own sake) — intrinsicalism and conditionalism. The former view (which is the one adopted by G.E. Moore and several later writers) holds that the final value of any F supervenes solely on features intrinsic to F, while the latter view allows that the final value of F may supervene on features non-intrinsic to F. Conditionalism thus allows the final value of F to vary according to …Read more
  •  239
    Buck-passing and the wrong kind of reasons
    Philosophical Quarterly 54 (215). 2004.
    According to T.M. Scanlon's buck-passing account of value, to be valuable is not to possess intrinsic value as a simple and unanalysable property, but rather to have other properties that provide reasons to take up an attitude in favour of their owner or against it. The 'wrong kind of reasons' objection to this view is that we may have reasons to respond for or against something without this having any bearing on its value. The challenge is to explain why such reasons are of the wrong kind. This…Read more
  •  73
    Non-Cognitivism and Fundamental Moral Certitude: Reply to Eriksson and Francén Olinder
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 95 (4): 794-799. 2017.
    Accommodating degrees of moral certitude is a serious problem for non-cognitivism about ethics. In particular, non-cognitivism has trouble accommodating fundamental moral certitude. John Eriksson and Ragnar Francén Olinder [2016] have recently proposed a solution. In fact, Eriksson and Francén Olinder offer two different proposals—one ‘classification’ account and one ‘projectivist’ account. We argue that the classification account faces the same problem as previous accounts do, while the project…Read more
  •  62
    The Personal and the Fitting
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 11 (3): 341-352. 2014.
    This paper is a critical notice of a recent significant contribution to the debate about fitting attitudes and value, namely Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen’s Personal Value. In this book, Rønnow-Rasmussen seeks to analyse the notion of personal value—an instance of the notion of good for a person—in terms of fitting attitudes. The paper has three main themes: Rønnow-Rasmussen’s discussion of general problems for fitting attitude analyses; his formulation of the fitting attitude analysis of personal value…Read more
  •  21
    Review of Simon Kirchin (ed.), Thick Concepts (Oxford University Press, 2013) (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. forthcoming.
  •  30
    Non-Naturalism
    In Simon Robertson (ed.), Spheres of Reason: New Essays in the Philosophy of Normativity, Oxford University Press. pp. 164. 2009.
  •  187
    Fitting Attitude Analyses of Value and the Partiality Challenge
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 12 (4): 365-378. 2009.
    According to ‘Fitting Attitude’ (FA) analyses of value, for an object to be valuable is for that object to have properties—other than its being valuable—that make it a fitting object of certain responses. In short, if an object is positively valuable it is fitting to favour it; if an object is negatively valuable it is fitting to disfavour it. There are several variants of FA analyses. Some hold that for an object to be valuable is for it to be such that it ought to be favoured; others hold that…Read more
  •  171
    Are desires de dicto fetishistic?
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 45 (1). 2002.
    In The Moral Problem Michael Smith presents what he claims is a decisive argument against moral externalism. Smith's claims that (i) moral externalists are committed to explain the connection between moral beliefs and moral motivation in terms of de dicto desires, and (ii) de dicto desires to perform moral acts amounts to moral fetishism. The argument is spelled out and the difference between desires de dicto and desires de re explained. The tenability of the fetishist argument (as it has been n…Read more
  •  68
    Against the Being For Account of Normative Certitude
    Journal of Ethics and Social Philosophy 6 (2): 1-8. 2012.
    Just as we can be more or less certain about empirical matters, we can be more or less certain about normative matters. Recently, it has been argued that this is a challenge for noncognitivism about normativity. Michael Smith presented the challenge in a 2002 paper and James Lenman and Michael Ridge responded independently. Andrew Sepielli has now joined the rescue operation. His basic idea is that noncognitivists should employ the notion of being for to account for normative certitude. We shall…Read more
  •  76
    Précis of Moral Error Theory: History, Critique, Defence
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 13 (4): 397-402. 2016.
    _ Source: _Volume 13, Issue 4, pp 397 - 402 Moral error theorists and moral realists agree about several disputed metaethical issues. They typically agree that ordinary moral judgments are beliefs and that ordinary moral utterances purport to refer to moral facts. But they disagree on the crucial ontological question of whether there are any moral facts. Moral error theorists hold that there are not and that, as a consequence, ordinary moral beliefs are systematically mistaken and ordinary moral…Read more
  •  549
    In defense of moral error theory
    In Michael Brady (ed.), New Waves in Metaethics, Palgrave-macmillan. 2010.
    My aim in this essay is largely defensive. I aim to discuss some problems for moral error theory and to offer plausible solutions. A full positive defense of moral error theory would require substantial investigations of rival metaethical views, but that is beyond the scope of this essay. I will, however, try to motivate moral error theory and to clarify its commitments. Moral error theorists typically accept two claims – one conceptual and one ontological – about moral facts. The conceptual cla…Read more