•  68
    Reply to Tenenbaum
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (3): 463-476. 2007.
  •  28
    Crazy Relations
    Croatian Journal of Philosophy 12 (3): 315-330. 2012.
    In The Red and the Real, Jonathan Cohen defends a relationalist view of color: the view that colors are constituted by relations between objects, perceivers, and circumstances. Cohen’s defense of relationalism is often ingenious, but it also commits him to some extremely counterintuitive—one might say “crazy”—claims. The present paper argues that the phenomena that are captured by Cohen’s ingenious defense of his interesting view can be captured equally well by a more “boring” view. Such a view …Read more
  •  106
    Putting particularism in its place
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 89 (3): 312-324. 2008.
    Abstract: The point of this paper is to undermine the support that particularism in the domain of epistemic reasons might seem to give to particularism in the domain of practical reasons. In the epistemic domain, there are two related notions: truth and the rationality of belief. Epistemic reasons are related to the rationality of belief, and not directly to truth. In the domain of practical reasons, however, the role of truth is taken by the notion of objective rationality. Practical reasons ar…Read more
  •  96
    Breaking the law of desire
    Erkenntnis 62 (3): 295-319. 2005.
    This paper offers one formal reason why it may often be inappropriate to hold, of two conflicting desires, that the first must be weaker than, stronger than, or of the same strength as the second. The explanation of this fact does not rely on vagueness or epistemological problems in determining the strengths of desires. Nor does it make use of the problematic notion of incommensurability. Rather, the suggestion is that the motivational capacities of many desires might best be characterized by tw…Read more
  • Naturalistic metaethics at half price
    In Michael Brady (ed.), New Waves in Metaethics, Palgrave-macmillan. 2010.
  •  161
    A realistic colour realism
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (4). 2006.
    Whether or not one endorses realism about colour, it is very tempting to regard realism about determinable colours such as green and yellow as standing or falling together with realism about determinate colours such as unique green or green31. Indeed some of the most prominent representatives of both sides of the colour realism debate explicitly endorse the idea that these two kinds of realism are so linked. Against such theorists, the present paper argues that one can be a realist about the det…Read more
  •  51
    Moral Rationalism and Commonsense Consequentialism
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (1): 217-224. 2014.
  •  46
    The Color of Mirrors
    American Philosophical Quarterly 43 (4). 2006.
    None
  •  167
    Many contemporary accounts of normative reasons for action accord a single strength value to normative reasons. This paper first uses some examples to argue against such views by showing that they seem to commit us to intransitive or counterintuitive claims about the rough equivalence of the strengths of certain reasons. The paper then explains and defends an alternate account according to which normative reasons for action have two separable dimensions of strength: requiring strength, and justi…Read more
  •  79
    Perform a Justified Option
    Utilitas 26 (2): 206-217. 2014.
    In a number of recent publications, Douglas Portmore has defended consequentialism, largely on the basis of a maximizing view of practical rationality. I have criticized such maximizing views, arguing that we need to distinguish two independent dimensions of normative strength: justifying strength and requiring strength. I have also argued that this distinction helps to explain why we typically have so many rational options. Engaging with these arguments, Portmore has (a) developed his own novel…Read more
  •  53
    Review of Normativity and the will by R. Jay Wallace (review)
    with Michael McKenna
    Philosophical Quarterly 58 (232). 2008.
  •  211
    What Colors Could Not Be
    Journal of Philosophy 105 (3): 128-155. 2008.
  •  72
    A Fitting End to the Wrong Kind of Reason Problem
    Ethics 126 (4): 1015-1042. 2016.
    This article uses a particular view of the basic emotions in order to develop and defend an account of paradigmatic emotion-linked evaluative properties. The view is that felt emotions are constituted by an awareness that one is about to behave in a certain way. This view provides support for a fitting-attitude account of certain evaluative properties. But the relevant sense of fittingness is not to be understood in terms of reasons. The account therefore sidesteps the well-known Wrong Kind of R…Read more
  •  42
    Mistaken expressions
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (4): 459-479. 2006.
    Florida State University, Tallahassee, FL 32306-1500 USA.
  •  24
    Many philosophers have argued that a necessary condition on an action's being intentional is that the agent has the ability to alter the probabilities of the relevant outcome. These philosophers would hold that this condition is what allows us to deny that an agent, for example, intentionally rolls something other than five fives with a set of dice, despite that agent's being virtually sure that this will be the outcome of the roll. The current paper uses some examples to cast this explanation, …Read more
  •  61
    Skepticism about Practical Reasons Internalism
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 39 (1): 59-77. 2001.
  •  67
    Disgust, Moral Disgust, and Morality
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 11 (4): 33-54. 2014.
    This paper calls into question the idea that moral disgust is usefully regarded as a form of genuine disgust. This hypothesis is questionable even if, as some have argued, the spread of moral norms through a community makes use of signaling mechanisms that are central to core disgust. The signaling system is just one part of disgust, and may well be completely separable from it. Moreover, there is plausibly a significant difference between the cognitive scientist’s concept of an emotion and the …Read more
  •  40
    Begging the Question: A Qualified Defense
    The Journal of Ethics 18 (3): 279-297. 2014.
    This discussion examines two of the central notions at work in Sterba’s From Rationality to Equality: question-beggingness, and the notion of a rational requirement. I point out that, against certain unreasonable positions, begging the question is a perfectly reasonable option. I also argue that if we use the sense of “rational requirement” that philosophers ought to have in mind when defending the idea that morality is rationally required, then Sterba has not succeed in defending this idea. Rat…Read more
  •  51
    Neo‐pragmatism, Representationalism and the Emotions
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 97 (2): 454-478. 2017.
    This paper offers a neo-pragmatist account of the representational character of the emotions, for those emotions that have such a character. Put most generally, neo-pragmatism is the view that language should not be conceived primarily in terms of a robust relation of reference to or representation of antecedently given objects and properties. Rather, we should view it as a social practice that lets us do various quite different sorts of things. One of those things might be called ‘assessing rep…Read more
  •  55
  •  86
    Avoiding the conditional fallacy
    Philosophical Quarterly 52 (206): 88-95. 2002.
    Over-simple internalist accounts of practical reasons imply that we cannot have reasons to become more rational, because they claim that we have a reason to φ only if we would have some desire to φ if we were fully rational. But if we were fully rational, we would have no desire to become more rational. Robert Johnson has recently argued that in their attempts to avoid this problem, existing versions of internalism yield reasons which do not have an appropriate connection with potential explanat…Read more
  •  11
    Moral Reasons and Rational Status
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 33 (sup1): 171-196. 2007.
    The question “Why be moral?” is open to at least three extremely different interpretations. One way to distinguish these interpretations is by picturing the question as being asked by, respectively, Allan, who is going to act immorally unless he can be convinced to act otherwise, Beth, who is perfectly happy to do what is morally required on a certain occasion but who wants to know what is it about the act that makes it morally required, and Charles, who is trying to understand why rational peop…Read more
  •  185
    Korsgaard’s Private-Reasons Argument
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (2): 303-324. 2002.
    In The Sources of Normativity, Christine Korsgaard presents and defends a neo-Kantian theory of normativity. Her initial account of reasons seems to make them dependent upon the practical identity of the agent, and upon the value the agent must place on her own humanity. This seems to make all reasons agent-relative. But Korsgaard claims that arguments similar to Wittgenstein’s private-language argument can show that reasons are in fact essentially agent-neutral. This paper explains both of Kors…Read more
  •  32
    The Myth of the Force of the Better Reason
    Southwest Philosophy Review 14 (1): 95-102. 1998.