•  13
    Moral Reasons and Rational Status
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 33 (sup1): 171-196. 2007.
    The question “Why be moral?” is open to at least three extremely different interpretations. One way to distinguish these interpretations is by picturing the question as being asked by, respectively, Allan, who is going to act immorally unless he can be convinced to act otherwise, Beth, who is perfectly happy to do what is morally required on a certain occasion but who wants to know what is it about the act that makes it morally required, and Charles, who is trying to understand why rational peop…Read more
  •  56
  •  180
    Korsgaard’s Private-Reasons Argument
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (2): 303-324. 2002.
    In The Sources of Normativity, Christine Korsgaard presents and defends a neo-Kantian theory of normativity. Her initial account of reasons seems to make them dependent upon the practical identity of the agent, and upon the value the agent must place on her own humanity. This seems to make all reasons agent-relative. But Korsgaard claims that arguments similar to Wittgenstein’s private-language argument can show that reasons are in fact essentially agent-neutral. This paper explains both of Kors…Read more
  •  32
    The Myth of the Force of the Better Reason
    Southwest Philosophy Review 14 (1): 95-102. 1998.
  •  18
    Engaging Reason (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66 (3): 745-748. 2003.
    First, some stage setting is necessary. According to Raz, what makes us into rational agents is our ability to perceive normative aspects of the world, appreciate their normative significance, and respond appropriately. Although he concentrates on the rationality of action, our beliefs, feelings, and emotions also demonstrate this ability. This characterization of his view already indicates that, according to Raz, the world indeed has normative aspects. What this means is that aspects of the wor…Read more
  •  109
    Response-dependence and normative bedrock
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79 (3): 718-742. 2009.
    No Abstract
  •  130
    Colour, emotion and objectivity
    Analysis 69 (4): 714-721. 2009.
    1. IntroductionThe Emotional Construction of Morals is a tour de force that combines empirical data and philosophical argument in an impressively coherent way. Certainly it resists any sweeping assessment; a mere presentation of the principal lines of argument would itself take the space of an article. Also, and despite its systematic structure, I do not think Prinz's view places decisive weight on any small number of points. Consequently, I do not think it can be refuted in any wholesale way. N…Read more
  •  53
    Problems for Moral Twin Earth Arguments
    Synthese 150 (2): 171-183. 2006.
    Terry Horgan and Mark Timmons have recently presented a series of papers in which they argue against what has come to be called the ‘new wave’ moral realism and moral semantics of David Brink, Richard Boyd, Peter Railton, and a number of other philosophers. The central idea behind Horgan and Timmons’s criticism of these ‘new wave’ theories has been extended by Sean Holland to include the sort of realism that drops out of response-dependent accounts that make use of an analogy between moral prope…Read more
  • Brute requirements
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 37 (1): 153-171. 2007.
  •  33
    A Functional Role Analysis of Reasons
    Philosophical Studies 124 (3): 353-378. 2005.
    One strategy for providing an analysis of practical rationality is to start with the notion of a practical reason as primitive. Then it will be quite tempting to think that the rationality of an action can be defined rather simply in terms of ‘the balance of reasons’. But just as, for many philosophical purposes, it is extremely useful to identify the meaning of a word in terms of the systematic contribution the word makes to the meanings of whole sentences, this paper argues that it is extremel…Read more
  • Mistaken Expressions
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (4): 459-479. 2006.
    It is a suggestive feature of English and other languages that an indicative sentence such as ‘Premarital sex is wrong’ can be described not only as an expression of the belief that premarital sex is wrong, but also as an expression of disapproval of premarital sex. Disapproval is plausibly regarded as an attitude that is distinct from belief, in that it does not have truth conditions. What sort of attitude, then, should we take ‘Premarital sex is wrong’ to express: disapproval, belief, or perha…Read more
  •  78
    Wittgenstein, Korsgaard and the Publicity of Reasons
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy (5): 1-21. 2013.
    Wittgenstein, Korsgaard and the Publicity of Reasons. . ???aop.label???. doi: 10.1080/0020174X.2013.776297
  •  116
    Toward an epistemology of certain substantive a priori truths
    Metaphilosophy 40 (2): 214-236. 2009.
    Abstract: This article explains and motivates an account of one way in which we might have substantive a priori knowledge in one important class of domains: domains in which the central concepts are response-dependent. The central example will be our knowledge of the connection between something's being harmful and the fact that it is irrational for us to fail to be averse to that thing. The idea is that although the relevant responses (basic aversion in the case of harm, and a kind of interpret…Read more
  •  53
    Desires, reasons, and rationality
    American Philosophical Quarterly 46 (4). 2009.
    Derek Parfit, Joseph Raz, and T. M. S canlon, among others, all hold that reasons for action are provided by facts about those actions. They also hold that the fact that an action would promote or achieve the object of an agent's desire is not one of the relevant facts, and does not provide a reason. Rather, the facts that provide reasons are typically facts about valuable states of affairs that the action is likely to bring about, or valuable properties that the action itself will instantiate. …Read more
  •  45
    Quality spaces: Mental and physical
    Philosophical Psychology 30 (5): 525-544. 2017.
    Perceptual-role theories of mental qualities hold that we can discover the nature of a being’s mental qualities by investigating that being’s capacity to make perceptual discriminations. Many advocates of perceptual-role theories hold that the best explanation of these capacities is that mental quality spaces are homomorphic to the spaces of the physical properties that they help to discriminate. This paper disputes this thesis on largely empirical grounds, and offers an alternative. The alterna…Read more
  •  86
    Color constancy and the color/value analogy
    Ethics 121 (1): 58-87. 2010.
    This article explains and defends the existence of value constancy, understood on the model of color constancy. Color constancy involves a phenomenal distinction between the transient color appearances of objects and the unchanging colors that those objects appear to have. The existence of value constancy allows advocates of response-dependent accounts of value to reject the question “What is the uniquely appropriate attitude to have toward this evaluative property?” as containing a false unique…Read more
  •  259
    Normative strength and the balance of reasons
    Philosophical Review 116 (4): 533-562. 2007.
  • Beyond Moore's Utilitarianism
    In Susana Nuccetelli & Gary Seay (eds.), Themes From G. E. Moore: New Essays in Epistemology and Ethics, Oxford University Press. 2007.
  •  158
    Moral Worth, Supererogation, and the Justifying/Requiring Distinction
    Philosophical Review 121 (4): 611-618. 2012.
    Julia Markovits has recently argued for what she calls the ‘Coincident Reasons Thesis’: the thesis that one’s action is morally worthy if and only if one’s motivating reasons for acting mirror, in content and strength, the reasons that explain why the action ought, morally, to be performed. This thesis assumes that the structure of motivating reasons is sufficiently similar to the structure of normative reasons that the required coincidence in content and strength is a genuine possibility. But b…Read more
  •  103
    One of us -- Alfred Mele (1996; 2003, ch. 5) -- has argued that possible instances of listlessness falsify the combination of cognitivism and various kinds of internalism about positive first-person moral ought-beliefs. If an argument recently advanced by James Lenman (1999) is successful, listlessnessis impossible and Mele's argument from listlessness therefore fails.However, we will argue that Lenman's argument is unpersuasive.
  •  117
    Value and parity
    Ethics 114 (3): 492-510. 2004.
  •  42
    Fine-Grained Colour Discrimination without Fine-Grained Colour
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 93 (3): 602-605. 2015.
    René Jagnow [2012] argues that David Rosenthal's theory of consciousness cannot account for certain experiences that involve colours so fine-grained that we do not and cannot have concepts of them. Jagnow claims that an appeal to comparative concepts such as being slightly darker than cannot help Rosenthal, since, in order to apply such concepts, we would already need to be conscious of two distinct fine-grained colours. The present paper contests this claim. It appeals to the Cornsweet illusion…Read more
  •  10
    Response‐Dependence and Normative Bedrock
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 79 (3): 718-742. 2009.
  •  13
  •  95
    Parity, Preference and Puzzlement
    Theoria 81 (3): 249-271. 2015.
    Ruth Chang has argued for the existence of a fourth positive value relation, distinct from betterness, worseness and equality, which she calls “parity.” In an earlier article I seemed to criticize Chang's suggestion by offering an interval model for the values of items that I claimed could accommodate all the phenomena characteristic of parity. Wlodek Rabinowicz, offering his own model of value relations, endorsed one central feature of my proposal: the need to distinguish permissible preference…Read more
  •  40
    Brute Rationality: Normativity and Human Action
    Cambridge University Press. 2004.
    This book presents an account of normative practical reasons and the way in which they contribute to the rationality of action. Rather than simply 'counting in favour of' actions, normative reasons play two logically distinct roles: requiring action and justifying action. The distinction between these two roles explains why some reasons do not seem relevant to the rational status of an action unless the agent cares about them, while other reasons retain all their force regardless of the agent's …Read more
  •  40
    Joshua Gert offers an original account of normative facts and properties, those which have implications for how we ought to behave. He argues that our ability to think and talk about normative notions such as reasons and benefits is dependent on how we respond to the world around us, including how we respond to the actions of other people