•  16
    Contrastive Explanations: A Dilemma for Libertarians
    Dialectica 59 (1): 51-61. 2005.
    To the extent that indeterminacy intervenes between our reasons for action and our decisions, intentions and actions, our freedom seems to be reduced, not enhanced. Free will becomes nothing more than the power to choose irrationally. In recognition of this problem, some recent libertarians have suggested that free will is paradigmatically manifested only in actions for which we have reasons for both or all the alternatives. In these circumstances, however we choose, we choose rationally. Agains…Read more
  •  162
    Cultural Membership and Moral Responsibility
    The Monist 86 (2): 145-163. 2003.
    Can our cultural membership excuse us from responsibility for certain actions? Ought the Aztec priest be held responsible for murder, for instance, or does the fact that his ritual sacrifice is mandated by his culture excuse him from blame? Our intuitions here are mixed; the more distant, historically and geographically, we are from those whose actions are in question, the more likely we are to forgive them their acts, yet it is difficult to pinpoint why this distance should excuse. Up close, hi…Read more
  •  90
    Countering Cova: Frankfurt-Style Cases are Still Broken
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17 (3): 523-527. 2014.
    In his “Frankfurt-style cases user manual”, Florian Cova (2013) distinguishes two kinds of Frankfurt-style arguments against the principle of alternative possibilities (PAP), and argues that my attack on the soundness of Frankfurt-style cases succeeds, at most, only against one kind. Since either kind of argument can be used to undermine PAP, Cova suggests, the fact that my attack fails against at least one means that it does not succeed in rescuing PAP from the clutches of Frankfurt enthusiasts…Read more
  •  144
    Contrastive explanations: A dilemma for libertarians
    Dialectica 59 (1): 51-61. 2005.
    To the extent that indeterminacy intervenes between our reasons for action and our decisions, intentions and actions, our freedom seems to be reduced, not enhanced. Free will becomes nothing more than the power to choose irrationally. In recognition of this problem, some recent libertarians have suggested that free will is paradigmatically manifested only in actions for which we have reasons for both or all the alternatives. In these circumstances, however we choose, we choose rationally. Agains…Read more
  •  14
    Countering Cova: Frankfurt-Style Cases are Still Broken
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 17 (3): 523-527. 2014.
    5 page
  •  761
    Book review: Understanding blindness (review)
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 3 (3): 315-324. 2004.
  •  58
  •  72
    In a recent paper, Ishtiyaque Haji and Michael McKenna argue that my attack on Frankfurt-style cases fails. I had argued that we cannot be confident that agents in these cases retain their responsibility-underwriting capacities, because what capacities an agent has can depend on features of the world external to her, including merely counterfactual interveners. Haji and McKenna argue that only when an intervention is actual does the agent gain or lose a capacity. Here I demonstrate that this cla…Read more
  •  135
    Bad Luck Once Again
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (3): 749-754. 2008.
    In a recent article in this journal, Storrs McCall and E.J. Lowe sketch an account of indeterminist free will designed to avoid the luck objection that has been wielded to such effect against event‐causal libertarianism. They argue that if decision‐making is an indeterministic process and not an event or series of events, the luck objection will fail. I argue that they are wrong: the luck objection is equally successful against their account as against existing event‐causal libertarianisms. Like…Read more
  •  105
    A Role for Consciousness After All
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 9 (2): 255-264. 2012.
    In a recent paper in this journal, Matt King and Peter Carruthers argue that the common assumption that agents are only (or especially) morally responsible for actions caused by attitudes of which they are conscious needs to be rethought. They claim that there is persuasive evidence that we are never conscious of our propositional attitudes; we ought therefore to design our theories of moral responsibility to accommodate this fact. In this reply, I argue that the evidence they adduce need not wo…Read more
  •  278
    A will of one's own: Consciousness, control, and character
    with Tim Bayne
    International Journal of Law and Psychiatry 27 (5): 459-470. 2004.
  •  184
    Against Philanthropy, Individual and Corporate
    Business and Professional Ethics Journal 21 (3-4): 95-108. 2002.
  • A Gresham's Law For Reporting About Genetics
    Australian Journal of Professional and Applied Ethics 4 (2). 2002.
  •  65
    Autonomy is (largely) irrelevant
    American Journal of Bioethics 9 (1). 2009.
    No abstract
  •  102
    Addiction, Autonomy, and Informed Consent: On and Off the Garden Path
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 41 (1): 56-73. 2015.
    Several ethicists have argued that research trials and treatment programs that involve the provision of drugs to addicts are prima facie unethical, because addicts can’t refuse the offer of drugs and therefore can’t give informed consent to participation. In response, several people have pointed out that addiction does not cause a compulsion to use drugs. However, since we know that addiction impairs autonomy, this response is inadequate. In this paper, I advance a stronger defense of the capaci…Read more
  •  10
    Addiction and Compulsion
    In T. O'Connor C. Sandis (ed.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Action, Blackwell. 2010.
    This chapter contains sections titled: References Further reading.
  •  73
    Agents and mechanisms: Fischer's way (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 57 (226). 2007.
  •  505
    Autonomy and addiction
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (3): 427-447. 2006.
    Centre for Applied Philosophy and Public Ethics University of Melbourne, Parkville, 3010, Australia and.
  •  266
    Addiction as a disorder of belief
    Biology and Philosophy 29 (3): 337-355. 2014.
    Addiction is almost universally held to be characterized by a loss of control over drug-seeking and consuming behavior. But the actions of addicts, even of those who seem to want to abstain from drugs, seem to be guided by reasons. In this paper, I argue that we can explain this fact, consistent with continuing to maintain that addiction involves a loss of control, by understanding addiction as involving an oscillation between conflicting judgments. I argue that the dysfunction of the mesolimbic…Read more
  •  38
    Autonomy and Addiction
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 36 (3): 427-447. 2006.
    Whatever its implications for the other features of human agency at its best — for moral responsibility, reasons-responsiveness, self-realization, flourishing, and so on—addiction is universally recognized as impairing autonomy. But philosophers have frequently misunderstood the nature of addiction, and therefore have not adequately explained the manner in which it impairs autonomy. Once we recognize that addiction is not incompatible with choice or volition, it becomes clear that none of the St…Read more
  •  223
    The feeling of doing: Deconstructing the phenomenology of agnecy
    with Timothy J. Bayne
    In Natalie Sebanz & Wolfgang Prinz (eds.), Disorders of Volition, Mit Press. 2006.
    Disorders of volition are often accompanied by, and may even be caused by, disruptions in the phenomenology of agency. Yet the phenomenology of agency is at present little explored. In this paper we attempt to describe the experience of normal agency, in order to uncover its representational content
  •  433
    In 1997, a Scottish surgeon by the name of Robert Smith was approached by a man with an unusual request: he wanted his apparently healthy lower left leg amputated. Although details about the case are sketchy, the would-be amputee appears to have desired the amputation on the grounds that his left foot wasn’t part of him – it felt alien. After consultation with psychiatrists, Smith performed the amputation. Two and a half years later, the patient reported that his life had been transformed for th…Read more