•  39
    Hans-Joachim Niemann, Karl Popper and the Two New Secrets of Life (review)
    Hopos: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 7 (1): 156-160. 2017.
  •  20
    Haldane and Mayr: a response to Rao and Nanjundiah
    History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences 38 (1): 151-154. 2016.
    The discussion with Rao and Nanjundiah about the history of interactions between J. B. S. Haldane and Ernst Mayr is further extended in this note. The nature of the dispute about beanbag genetics is explicated as consisting of two separate issues, one about the role of mathematical analysis in evolutionary biology, and the other about the value of single-locus genic models.
  •  2
  •  8
    Flights of fancy Content Type Journal Article Pages 1-2 DOI 10.1007/s11016-011-9572-y Authors Sahotra Sarkar, Section of Integrative Biology, Department of Philosophy, University of Texas at Austin, Waggener Hall 316, Austin, TX 78712-1180, USA Journal Metascience Online ISSN 1467-9981 Print ISSN 0815-0796
  •  7
    Formal Darwinism: Some questions
    Biology and Philosophy 29 (2): 249-257. 2014.
    Two questions are raised for Grafen’s formal darwinism project of aligning evolutionary dynamics under natural selection with the optimization of phenotypes for individuals of a population. The first question concerns mean fitness maximization during frequency-dependent selection; in such selection regimes, not only is mean fitness typically not maximized but it is implausible that any parameter closely related to fitness is being maximized. The second question concerns whether natural selection…Read more
  •  16
    Evolutionary theory in the 1920s: The nature of the “synthesis”
    Philosophy of Science 71 (5): 1215-1226. 2004.
    This paper analyzes the development of evolutionary theory in the period from 1918 to 1932. It argues that: (i) Fisher's work in 1918 constituted a not fully satisfactory reduction of biometry to Mendelism; (ii) there was a synthesis in the 1920s but that this synthesis was mainly one of classical genetics with population genetics, with Haldane's The Causes of Evolution being its founding document; (iii) the most important achievement of the models of theoretical population genetics was to show …Read more
  •  9
    Environmental philosophy: Response to critics
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 45 (1): 105-109. 2014.
    The following piece is a response to the critiques from Frank, Garson, and Odenbaugh. The issues at stake are: the definition of biodiversity and its normativity, historical fidelity in ecological restoration, naturalism in environmental ethics, and the role of decision theory. The normativity of the concept of biodiversity in conservation biology is defended. Historical fidelity is criticized as an operative goal for ecological restoration. It is pointed out that the analysis requires only mini…Read more
  •  48
    The first comprehensive treatment of environmental philosophy, going beyond ethics to address the philosophical concepts that underlie environmental thinking and policy-making today Encompasses all of environmental philosophy, including conservation biology, restoration ecology, sustainability, environmental justice, and more Offers the first treatment of decision theory in an environmental philosophy text Explores the conceptions of nature and ethical presuppositions that underlie contemporary …Read more
  •  17
    Environmental philosophy: From theory to practice
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 45 (1): 89-91. 2014.
    Environmental philosophy is a hybrid discipline drawing extensively from epistemology, ethics, and philosophy of science and analyzing disciplines such as conservation biology, restoration ecology, sustainability studies, and political ecology. The book being discussed both provides an overview of environmental philosophy and develops an anthropocentric framework for it. That framework treats natural values as deep cultural values. Tradeoffs between natural values are analyzed using decision the…Read more
  •  13
    Ricotta argues against the existence of a unique measure of biodiversity by pointing out that no known measure of α-diversity satisfies all the adequacy conditions that have traditionally been set for it. While that technical claim is correct, it is not relevant in the context of defining biodiversity which is most usefully measured by β-diversity. The concept of complementarity provides a closely related family of measures of biodiversity which can be used for systematic conservation planning. …Read more
  •  10
    Evolution by association: A history of symbiosis
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 29 (1): 211-218. 1998.
  •  5
    Evolution by association: A history of symbiosis - Jan Sapp, (new York and oxford: Oxford university press, 1994), XVII + 255 pp. ISBN 0-19-508820-4 cloth; 0-19-508821-2 paperback £19.95 (review)
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 29 (1): 211-218. 1998.
  •  44
    David Malament's (1977) well-known result, which is often taken to show the uniqueness of the Poincare-Einstein convention for defining simultaneity, involves an unwarranted physical assumption: that any simultaneity relation must remain invariant under temporal reflections. Once that assumption is removed, his other criteria for defining simultaneity are also satisfied by membership in the same backward (forward) null cone of the family of such cones with vertices on an inertial path. What is t…Read more
  •  12
    Frank has recently argued for an information-theoretic interpretation of natural selection. This interpretation is based on the identification of a measure related to the Malthusian parameter (for population change) with the Jeffreys divergence between the present allelic distribution of the population and that distribution in the next generation. It is pointed out in this analysis that this identification only holds if the mean fitness of the population is a constant, that is, there is no selec…Read more
  •  8
    Norton has argued for the salience of deliberative strategies for making environmental decisions which is supposed to be preferable to formal decision analysis. This paper argues that formal multicriteria decision analysis, when deployed with care, has the flexibility to absorb the advantages of deliberative decision making. It can also be used for decision support during a deliberative process. This feature of decision analysis is illustrated using a case study from Merauke in Papua province of…Read more
  •  29
    Defining “Biodiversity”; Assessing Biodiversity
    The Monist 85 (1): 131-155. 2001.
    This paper analyzes the concept of biodiversity in conservation biology and assesses potential methods for its measurement.
  •  5
    Conceptual Foundations of Organization Theory (review)
    Philosophical Review 101 (2): 484-485. 1992.
  •  10
    Carnap and the compulsions of interpretation: Reining in the liberalization of empiricism (review)
    European Journal for Philosophy of Science 3 (3): 353-372. 2013.
    Carnap’s work was instrumental to the liberalization of empiricism in the 1930s that transformed the logical positivism of the Vienna Circle to what came to be known as logical empiricism. A central feature of this liberalization was the deployment of the Principle of Tolerance, originally introduced in logic, but now invoked in an epistemological context in “Testability and Meaning”. Immediately afterwards, starting with Foundations of Logic and Mathematics, Carnap embraced semantics and turned…Read more
  •  5
    This paper reconstructs the history of the introduction and use of iterative algorithms in conservation biology in the 1980s and early 1990s in order to prioritize areas for protection as nature reserves. The importance of these algorithms was that they led to greater economy in spatial extent (“efficiency”) in the selection of areas to represent biological features adequately (that is, to a specified level) compared to older methods of scoring and ranking areas using criteria such as biotic “ri…Read more
  •  3
    Biology and philosophy special issue for 2003 – evolution and development
    with JasonScott Robert
    Biology and Philosophy 16 (4): 573-573. 2001.
  •  18
    A note on frequency dependence and the levels/units of selection
    Biology and Philosophy 23 (2): 217-228. 2008.
    On the basis of distinctions between those properties of entities that can be defined without reference to other entities and those that (in different ways) cannot, this note argues that non-trivial forms of frequency-dependent selection of entities should be interpreted as selection occurring at a level higher than that of those entities. It points out that, except in degenerately simple cases, evolutionary game-theoretic models of selection are not models of individual selection. Similarly, mo…Read more
  •  47
    A Sustainable Philosophy—the Work of Bryan Norton (edited book)
    with Ben A. Minteer
    Springer Verlag. 2018.
    This book provides a richly interdisciplinary assessment of the thought and work of Bryan Norton, one of most innovative and influential environmental philosophers of the past thirty years. In landmark works such as Toward Unity Among Environmentalists and Sustainability: A Philosophy of Adaptive Ecosystem Management, Norton charted a new and highly productive course for an applied environmental philosophy, one fully engaged with the natural and social sciences as well as the management professi…Read more
  •  12
    Learning Material Annotation for Flexible Tutoring System
    with D. Roy and S. Ghose
    Journal of Intelligent Systems 16 (4): 293-306. 2007.
  •  20
    How development may direct evolution
    Biology and Philosophy 18 (2): 353-370. 2003.
    A framework is presented in which the role ofdevelopmental rules in phenotypic evolution canbe studied for some simple situations. Usingtwo different implicit models of development,characterized by different developmental mapsfrom genotypes to phenotypes, it is shown bysimulation that developmental rules and driftcan result in directional phenotypic evolutionwithout selection. For both models thesimulations show that the critical parameterthat drives the final phenotypic distributionis the cardi…Read more
  •  7
    The real objective of Mendel's paper: A response to Monaghan and Corcos (review)
    with Raphael Falk
    Biology and Philosophy 6 (4): 447-451. 1991.
    Mendel's work in hybridization is ipso facto a study in inheritance. He is explicit in his interest to formulate universal generalizations, and at least in the case of the independent segregation of traits, he formulated his conclusions in the form of a law. Mendel did not discern, however, the inheritance of traits from that of the potential for traits. Choosing to study discrete non-overlapping traits, this did not hamper his efforts.
  •  3
    Harmony from discord
    with Raphal Falk
    Biology and Philosophy 7 (4): 463-472. 1992.