•  42
    Outline of the Argument REASON IS NOT passion's slave. In his famous statement to the contrary Hume supposed that reason labours only to satisfy our wants, ...
  •  70
    Reasonable Trust
    European Journal of Philosophy 21 (3): 402-423. 2013.
    Establishing trust among individual agents has defined a central issue of practical reasoning since the dawning of liberal individualism. Hobbes was convinced that foolish self-interest always threatens to defeat uncompelled cooperation when one can gain by abandoning a joint effort. Against this philosophical background, scientific studies of human beings display a surprisingly cooperative species. It would seem to follow that biologically inherited characteristics impair our reason. The respon…Read more
  •  21
    Patterns of Moral Complexity (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 19 (2): 309-324. 1989.
  •  37
    Practical Reasonableness: Some Metaethical Issues
    Journal of Value Inquiry 47 (4): 425-437. 2013.
    Normative judgments are typically subject to emotional reasons that cannot be justified by reference to facts alone. As a result, practical disputes sometimes go unsettled in ways that support James Lenman's view of moral inquiry as politics. An important consequence is that reasonableness is often preferable to truth as a criterion of good practical judgment. Although the role of emotions suggests metaethical expressivism as preferable to realism for analysing practical reasoning, reasonablenes…Read more
  •  68
    Prudence and Anti-Prudence
    American Philosophical Quarterly 35 (1). 1998.
    This article identifies both prudence and antiprudence as options for rational people. Building upon Wiggins's "sensible subjectivism," the account offers an analysis of prudential emotions which are not rationally required but whose reasonableness need not be doubted. One result is that skepticism about prudence is avoidable. Another, as shown through examination of some of Parfit's worries about replication, is that prudence is autonomous from metaphysical theories of persons. It is also auton…Read more
  •  35
    Practical Reasonableness: Some Epistemic Issues
    Journal of Value Inquiry 47 (1-2): 135-145. 2013.
    This essay promotes the superiority of cognitivist expressivism over noncognitivism and normative realism. Cognitivist expressivism regards normative judgments as emotionally reasonable but non-truth-apt. It stresses a distinction between normative differences and disagreements and rejects several contrasting views: communicative rationalism, discursive nonnaturalism, and moral universalism. It also explains why moral thinking often appears to display a progressive direction but questions the pr…Read more
  •  46
    Objective Reason and Respect for Persons
    The Monist 62 (4): 457-469. 1979.
    Objectivity in evaluation can be understood either in terms of satisfaction of certain formal criteria or in terms of correspondence to facts of a certain kind. Morality includes metaphysical claims which distinguish arbitrary wants from rational ends, but the weakness of the interpretation of such claims within formalist liberal views results in the collapse of that distinction and in mistaking moral ignorance for moral freedom. Only by showing that respect for persons is justified by the meta…Read more
  •  8
    Liberty, Democracy, Community
    Public Affairs Quarterly 6 (3): 327-344. 1992.
    Liberal and communitarian democrats describe different ways in which liberty, democracy, and community might exist together in political associations. The modern differentiation of political associations from traditional communities favours liberal accounts, in which a democratic society's collective acts do not extend beyond the official decisions of elected governments. While participatory self-rule does not seem possible at the level of the nation-state, however, there remain analogues to com…Read more
  •  2
    John Ibberson, The Language of Decision Reviewed by
    Philosophy in Review 7 (12): 498-500. 1987.
  •  10
    Critical Notice
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 19 (2): 309-324. 1989.
  •  232
    Between internalism and externalism in ethics
    Philosophical Quarterly 49 (195): 201-214. 1999.
    If internalism in ethics is correct, then moral beliefs necessarily motivate. Externalism rejects this thesis, holding that the relationship between beliefs and motives is only contingent. The position I develop is that both views are false. By defining a logical relationship between moral beliefs and motives that is weaker than logical necessitation, it is possible to maintain (contrary to internalism) that beliefs may occur without motives, but (contrary to externalism) that they cannot always…Read more
  •  19
    Rights Thinking
    Philosophy 72 (279). 1997.
    The practice of rights thinking is desirable in modern societies but its scope is restricted by concern for utility and the demands of personal relationships. The result is a hybrid practice no part of which is a foundation for the others. Differences between pure rights thinking, theories of rights and rights talk support a moral pragmatism for which the objects of moral thinking are not decided a priori. The argument draws upon the historical context provided by Bentham, Burke, Locke and Marx.…Read more
  •  26
    Anti-Theory in Ethics and Moral Conservatism (edited book)
    with Stanley G. Clarke
    State University of New York Press. 1989.
    "This is a timely collection of important papers.
  •  17
    An Analysis of Certainty
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 6 (3). 1976.
    Ever since Moore revived the gospel of certainty, philosophers content with commonsense have tried to provide a perspicuous formulation of its merits. Neither Moore nor his ablest successors have completely fulfilled this task, and although few philosophers would take up Wittgenstein's challenge, “Just try ——in a real case ——to doubt someone else's fear or pain”, many would disagree that if one does he will “find these words becoming quite meaningless”. The psychological conviction that men have…Read more
  •  16
    Aesthetic Appraisal
    Philosophy 50 (192). 1975.
    In the twenty-five years since philosophers began to bemoan ‘the dreariness of aesthetics’, students in Wittgenstein's wake have done a great deal to eliminate the grounds of the complaint. Unfruitful essentialist theories have been largely displaced by the vigorous, if somewhat uncontrolled, growth of an enterprise which attempts to characterize and explicate aesthetic phenomena outside the desert of definition. The resulting view portrays typically aesthetic concepts as being indivisibly chara…Read more