• University of Exeter
    Department of Sociology, Philosophy and Anthropology
    Egenis, Centre for the Study of Life Sciences
    Professor
United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland
  •  105
    Human nature and the limits of science
    Oxford University Press. 2001.
    John Dupre warns that our understanding of human nature is being distorted by two faulty and harmful forms of pseudo-scientific thinking. Not just in the academic world but in everyday life, we find one set of experts who seek to explain the ends at which humans aim in terms of evolutionary theory, while the other set uses economic models to give rules of how we act to achieve those ends. Dupre demonstrates that these theorists' explanations do not work and that, if taken seriously, their theori…Read more
  •  104
    Size doesn’t matter: towards a more inclusive philosophy of biology (review)
    with Maureen A. O’Malley
    Biology and Philosophy 22 (2): 155-191. 2007.
    Philosophers of biology, along with everyone else, generally perceive life to fall into two broad categories, the microbes and macrobes, and then pay most of their attention to the latter. ‘Macrobe’ is the word we propose for larger life forms, and we use it as part of an argument for microbial equality. We suggest that taking more notice of microbes – the dominant life form on the planet, both now and throughout evolutionary history – will transform some of the philosophy of biology’s standard …Read more
  •  101
    Fundamental issues in systems biology
    with Maureen A. O'Malley
    Bioessays 27 (12): 1270-1276. 2005.
    In the context of scientists' reflections on genomics, we examine some fundamental issues in the emerging postgenomic discipline of systems biology. Systems biology is best understood as consisting of two streams. One, which we shall call ‘pragmatic systems biology’, emphasises large‐scale molecular interactions; the other, which we shall refer to as ‘systems‐theoretic biology’, emphasises system principles. Both are committed to mathematical modelling, and both lack a clear account of what biol…Read more
  •  100
    Against reductionist explanations of human behaviour: John dupré
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 72 (1). 1998.
    [John Dupré] This paper attacks some prominent contemporary attempts to provide reductive accounts of ever wider areas of human behaviour. In particular, I shall address the claims of sociobiology (or evolutionary psychology) to provide a universal account of human nature, and attempts to subsume ever wider domains of behaviour within the scope of economics. I shall also consider some recent suggestions as to how these approaches might be integrated. Having rejected the imperialistic ambitions o…Read more
  •  97
    Understanding Contemporary Genomics
    Perspectives on Science 12 (3): 320-338. 2004.
    Recent molecular biology has seen the development of genomics as a successor to traditional genetics. This paper offers an overview of the structure, epistemology, and history of contemporary genomics. A particular focus is on the question to what extent the genome contains, or is composed of, anything that corresponds to traditional conceptions of genes. It is concluded that the only interpretation of genes that has much contemporary scientific relevance is what is described as the "development…Read more
  •  95
    Animalism and the Persistence of Human Organisms
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 52 (S1): 6-23. 2014.
    Humans are a kind of animal, and it is a natural and sensible idea that the way to understand what it is for a human person to persist over time is to reflect on what it is for an animal to persist. This paper accepts this strategy. However, especially in the light of a range of recent biological findings, the persistence of animals turns out to be much more problematic than is generally supposed. The main philosophical premise of the paper is that living systems generally are best treated as pr…Read more
  •  95
    Understanding viruses: Philosophical investigations
    with Thomas Pradeu and Gladys Kostyrka
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 59 57-63. 2016.
    Viruses have been virtually absent from philosophy of biology. In this editorial introduction, we explain why we think viruses are philosophically important. We focus on six issues, and we show how they relate to classic questions of philosophy of biology and even general philosophy.
  •  94
    A process ontology for biology
    The Philosophers' Magazine 67 81-88. 2014.
  •  93
    The gene myth (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 25 (25): 59-59. 2004.
  •  92
    What Fodor got wrong (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 50 (50): 118-120. 2010.
  •  90
    The Lure of the Simplistic
    Philosophy of Science 69 (S3). 2002.
    This paper attacks the perennial philosophical and scientific quest for a simple and unified vision of the world. Without denying the attraction of this vision, I argue that such a goal often seriously distorts our understanding of complex phenomena. The argument is illustrated with reference to simplistic attempts to provide extremely general views of biology, and especially of human nature, through the theory of evolution. Although that theory is a fundamental ingredient of our scientific worl…Read more
  •  87
    Against scientific imperialism
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1994. 1994.
    Most discussion of the unity of science has concerned what might be called vertical relations between theories: the reducibility of biology to chemistry, or chemistry to physics, and so on. In this paper I shall be concerned rather with horizontal relations, that is to say, with theories of different kinds that deal with objects at the same structural level. Whereas the former, vertical, conception of unity through reduction has come under a good deal of criticism recently (see, e.g., Dupré 1993…Read more
  •  81
    Probabilistic Causality Emancipated
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 9 (1): 169-175. 1984.
  •  80
    Wittgenstein and Forms of Life
    The Philosophers' Magazine 4 (4): 24-27. 1998.
  •  80
    John Dupr explores recent revolutionary developments in biology and considers their relevance for our understanding of human nature and society. He reveals how the advance of genetic science is changing our view of the constituents of life, and shows how an understanding of microbiology will overturn standard assumptions about the living world
  •  78
    Science and values and values in science: Comments on Philip Kitcher's science, truth, and democracy
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 47 (5). 2004.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  78
    Probabilistic Causality: A Rejoinder to Ellery Eells
    Philosophy of Science 57 (4). 1990.
    In an earlier paper (Dupré 1984), I criticized a thesis sometimes defended by theorists of probabilistic causality, namely, that a probabilistic cause must raise the probability of its effect in every possible set of causally relevant background conditions (the "contextual unanimity thesis"). I also suggested that a more promising analysis of probabilistic causality might be sought in terms of statistical relevance in a fair sample. Ellery Eells (1987) has defended the contextual unanimity thesi…Read more
  •  78
    The philosophical basis of biological classification
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (2): 271-279. 1994.
  •  72
    You must have thought this book was about you1: Reply to Daniel Dennett
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 70 (3). 2005.
    Daniel Dennett’s review of my book, Human Nature and the Limits of Science, was apparently conceived as part of a multiple review, anticipating an author’s response, so I am grateful for the opportunity to satisfy this expectation. Indeed, Dennett uses this excuse to justify devoting his own contribution to responding to those parts of the book directed explicitly at his own work, leaving other imagined reviewers to take care of other issues. Since he has things to say about most of the topics i…Read more
  •  69
    Could There Be a Science of Economics?
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 18 (1): 363-378. 1993.
    Much scientific thinking and thinking about science involves assumptions that there is a deep and pervasive order to the world that it is the business of science to disclose. A paradigmatic statement of such a view can be found in a widely discussed paper by a prominent economist, Milton Friedman (a paper which will be discussed in more detail shortly): A fundamental hypothesis of science is that appearances are deceptive and that there is a way of looking at or interpreting or organizing the ev…Read more
  •  69
    Viruses as living processes
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 59 109-116. 2016.
  •  65
    Human reproduction and sociobiology
    Analysis 43 (4): 210-212. 1983.
  •  64
    Humans and Other Animals
    Clarendon Press. 2002.
    John Dupré explores the ways in which we categorize animals, including humans, and comes to refreshingly radical conclusions. He opposes the idea that there is only one legitimate way of classifying things in the natural world, the 'scientific' way. The lesson we should learn from Darwin is to reject the idea that each organism has an essence that determines its necessary place in the unique hierarchy of things. Nature is not like that: it is not organized in a single system. For instance, there…Read more
  •  64
    Natural Kinds and Biological Taxa
    The Philosophical Review 90 (1): 66-90. 1981.