•  74
    Open Your Eyes?
    Film and Philosophy 14 33-46. 2010.
  •  14
    Nietzsche has often been interpreted as criticizing Buddhism for its pessimistic nihilism, since it supposedly aims at the otherworldly goal of nirvanaand the extinction of suffering. This article tries to adjust this view by focusing on the aspects of Buddhism of which Nietzsche implicitly or explicitly approves. It also relates these to some striking similarities between their views of the world, the individual, life in general and how to deal with it. This article shows that Nietzsche, in his…Read more
  •  19
    Rationality and institutions: an inquiry into the normative implications of rational choice theory
    Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics 1 (1): 185. 2008.
    I aim to analyze in this dissertation what a desirable basic institutional structure looks like from the perspective of rationality. While the main topic is thus normative in nature, I start by clarifying in the first part what the notion of rationality exactly entails. I do so by focusing explicitly on the economic conception of rationality, according to which a rational individual is motivated to serve his self-interest on the basis of cost-benefit calculations. Such a Homo Economicus is chara…Read more
  •  24
    Een kritische vergelijking Van twee levensfilosofieën
    Bijdragen 67 (3): 288-308. 2006.
  •  21
    A new definition of and role for preferences in positive economics
    Journal of Economic Methodology 24 (3): 254-273. 2017.
    Positive economic models aim to provide truthful explanations of significant economic phenomena. While the notion of ‘preferences’ figures prominently in micro-economic models, it suffers from a remarkable lack of conceptual clarity and rigor. After distinguishing narrow homo economicus models from broader ones and rehearsing the criticisms both have met, I go into the most promising attempt to date at addressing them, developed by Hausman. However, his definition of preferences as ‘total compar…Read more