•  48
    Hume on Heaps and Bundles
    American Philosophical Quarterly 16 (4). 1979.
  •  98
    Natural Virtues, Natural Vices: ANNETTE C. BAIER
    Social Philosophy and Policy 8 (1): 24-34. 1990.
    David Hume has been invoked by those who want to found morality on human nature as well as by their critics. He is credited with showing us the fallacy of moving from premises about what is the case to conclusions about what ought to be the case; and yet, just a few pages after the famous is-ought remarks in A Treatise of Human Nature, he embarks on his equally famous derivation of the obligations of justice from facts about the cooperative schemes accepted in human communities. Is he ambivalent…Read more
  •  306
    Act and intent
    Journal of Philosophy 67 (19): 648-658. 1970.
  •  260
    What emotions are about
    Philosophical Perspectives 4 1-29. 1990.
  • Hume, David (1711–1776)
    In Lawrence C. Becker & Charlotte B. Becker (eds.), Encyclopedia of ethics, Routledge. pp. 2--803. 1992.
  •  227
    Moralism and cruelty: Reflections on Hume and Kant
    Ethics 103 (3): 436-457. 1993.
    Both a morality, like Kant's, which relies on wrongdoers' guilt feelings and expectation of punishment, as enforcement for its requirements, and one which, like Hume's, relies on the feelings of shame and expectation of their fellows' contempt which will be felt by those showing lack of the moral virtues, seem to merit the charge that morality is an intrinsically cruel institution. The prospects for a gentle non-punitive morality are explored, and Hume's views found more promising, for this purp…Read more
  •  192
    Trusting people
    Philosophical Perspectives 6 137-153. 1992.
  •  39
    Frankena and Hume on Points of View
    The Monist 64 (3): 342-358. 1981.
    Frankena sees moral point of view theories as steering a middle course between scepticism or relativism in ethics and absolutism or dogmatism. The constraints of a distinctive point of view limit the range of moral judgments, provide some basis to expect agreement between different moral judges, and generate standards if not of moral truth at least of moral acceptability. Since however these constraints arise only from the moral point of view, they are avoidable if the point of view is avoidable…Read more
  •  1
    David Hume
    In Lawrence C. Becker & Charlotte B. Becker (eds.), Encyclopedia of ethics, Routledge. 1992.
  •  16
    Response to Dancy
    Philosophical Books 36 (4): 243-245. 1995.
  •  7
  •  44
    Pilgrim's Progress (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (2): 315-330. 1988.
  • Hume's excellent hypocrites
    In E. Mazza & Ronchetti (eds.), Rivista di Storia Della Filosofia, Francoangeli. pp. 267-286. 2007.
  • Master Passions
    In Amelia Oksenberg Rorty (ed.), Explaining Emotions, University of California Press. 1980.
  •  95
    Hume's account of our absurd passions
    Journal of Philosophy 79 (11): 643-651. 1982.
  •  39
    The Need for More Than Justice
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 13 (n/a): 41-56. 1987.
    In recent decades in North American social and moral philosophy, alongside the development and discussion of widely influential theories of justice, taken as Rawls takes it as the ‘first virtue of social institutions,’ there has been a counter-movement gathering strength, one coming from some interesting sources. For some of the most outspoken of the diverse group who have in a variety of ways been challenging the assumed supremacy of justice among the moral and social virtues are members of tho…Read more
  •  113
    Some Thoughts on How We Moral Philosophers Live Now
    The Monist 67 (4): 490-497. 1984.
    Philosophers have always seen at least part of their job to be social criticism, where by that I mean not necessarily negative assessment of existing social practices, but rather the attempt to understand them, to see existing local ones against a background of other possibilities. Included among these surveyed practices are, or should be, practices of justification and criticism, our own included. Socrates set the standard when, in the Apology and Crito he turned his method on his own activity,…Read more
  •  4
    Critical Notice (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (3): 589-594. 1988.
  •  101
    Hume’s Touchstone
    Hume Studies 36 (1): 51-60. 2010.
    At the end of part 3 of Book 1 of his Treatise,1 Hume had given a touchstone by which to judge any account of the human mind, namely that, where other animals appear to display the same cognitive operation that we do, our account applies as well to them as to us.2 He tests his own account of causal inference this way and finds that it comes through with flying colors, since the effects of experience of constant conjunctions on animal minds is just as he has claimed it to be on ours. Some of thei…Read more
  •  16
    Barbara Herman., The Practice of Moral Judgments
    International Studies in Philosophy 28 (2): 139-140. 1996.
  •  58
    Hume on Resentment
    Hume Studies 6 (2): 133-149. 1980.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:133. HUME ON RESENTMENT In his Enquiry version of the conditions of justice, Hume adds a third modified Hobbesian condition to the two, moderate scarcity and moderate selfishness, which he had listed in the Treatise. The new condition is a certain measure of equality, or limit ±o inequality—justice is owed, he says, only if there is a society of more-or-less equals; and only to those who are members of it. The equality in question co…Read more
  •  25
    Persons: A Study in Philosophical Psychology
    with Raziel Abelson
    Philosophical Review 88 (1): 112. 1979.