•  176
    The Natural History of Desire
    South African Journal of Philosophy 34 (3): 304-313. 2015.
    Sterelny (2003) develops an idealised natural history of folk-psychological kinds. He argues that belief-like states are natural elaborations of simpler control systems, called detection systems, which map directly from environmental cue to response. Belief-like states exhibit robust tracking (sensitivity to multiple environmental states), and response breadth (occasioning a wider range of behaviours). The development of robust tracking and response-breadth depend partly on properties of the inf…Read more
  •  11
    Editorial
    with Deane-Peter Baker and Simon Beck
    South African Journal of Philosophy 24 (2): 61-63. 2005.
  •  572
    A recurring claim in a number of behavioural, cognitive and neuro-scientific literatures is that there is, or must be, a unidimensional ‘common currency’ in which the values of different available options are represented. There is striking variety in the quantities or properties that have been proposed as determinants of the ordering in motivational strength. Among those seriously suggested are pain and pleasure, biological fitness, reward and reinforcement, and utility among economists, who hav…Read more
  •  422
    How to do things without words
    with S. J. Cowley
    Language Sciences 26 (5): 443-466. 2004.
    Clark and Chalmers (1998) defend the hypothesis of an ‘Extended Mind’, maintaining that beliefs and other paradigmatic mental states can be implemented outside the central nervous system or body. Aspects of the problem of ‘language acquisition’ are considered in the light of the extended mind hypothesis. Rather than ‘language’ as typically understood, the object of study is something called ‘utterance-activity’, a term of art intended to refer to the full range of kinetic and prosodic features o…Read more
  •  11
    Текущая сессия контакты копирайт
    South African Journal of Philosophy 18 (2): 258-274. 1999.
    I don't know what this document is. I'm not aware of ever being translated into Russian, but the issue and pagination suggest it refers to my review article of Cilliers' "Complexity and Postmodernism". That article is correctly indexed elsewhere on this site.
  •  62
    What about embodiment?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (5): 620-620. 2003.
    I present reasons for adding an embodiment criterion to the list defended by Anderson & Lebiere (A&L). I also entertain a likely objection contending that embodiment is merely a type of dynamic behavior and is therefore covered by the target article. In either case, it turns out that neither connectionism nor ACT-R do particularly well when it comes to embodiment.
  •  50
    It's not just the subjects–there are too many WEIRD researchers
    with Michael Meadon
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (2-3): 104-105. 2010.
    A literature in which most data are outliers is flawed, and the target article sounds a timely alarm call for the behavioural sciences. It also suggests remedies. We mostly concur, except for arguing that the importance of the fact that the researchers themselves are mostly outliers has been underplayed. Improving matters requires non-Western researchers, as well as research subjects
  •  36
    Review of Burns, J. The Descent of Madness: Evolutionary Origins of Psychosis and the Social Brain (review)
    South African Journal of Philosophy 28 (2): 257-258. 2009.
    Review of Burns, J. The Descent of Madness: Evolutionary Origins of Psychosis and the Social Brain (London: Routledge, 2007)
  •  36
    Need there be a common currency for decision-making?
    South African Journal of Philosophy 28 (2): 210-221. 2009.
    According to various theorists and empirical scholars of behavior and decision, including economists, utility theorists, behavioral ecologists, behavioral economists and researchers in the new field of neuroeconomics the value (typically understood as utility) of competing choices must be represented on a common scale in order for them to count as competing at all, and in order for orderly comparison to lead to actual choices. For some neuroeconomists this means that expected (cardinal) utilitie…Read more
  •  612
    Cartwright on laws and composition
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15 (3). 2000.
    Cartwright attempts to argue from an analysis of the composition of forces, and more generally the composition of laws, to the conclusion that laws must be regarded as false. A response to Cartwright is developed which contends that properly understood composition poses no threat to the truth of laws, even though agreeing with Cartwright that laws do not satisfy the "facticity" requirement. My analysis draws especially on the work of Creary, Bhaskar, Mill, and points towards a general rejection …Read more
  •  641
    What Physical Properties Are
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 82 (2): 201-225. 2001.
    This paper concerns the question of how to specify what is to count as physical for the purposes of debates concerning either physicalism or the completeness of physics. I argue that what is needed from an account of the physical depends primarily on the particular issue at stake, and that the demand for a general a priori specification of the physical is misplaced. A number of attempts to say what should be counted as physical are defended from recent attacks by Chris Daly, and a specific proposa…Read more
  •  4
  •  19
    Transcendental realism defended: a response to Allan
    South African Journal of Philosophy 17 (3): 198-210. 1998.
  •  36
    Editorial: New Developments at the SAJP
    with Deane-Peter Baker and Simon Beck
    South African Journal of Philosophy 25 (2): 89-90. 2006.
  •  39
    Reductionisms and physicalisms
    South African Journal of Philosophy 25 (2): 159-170. 2006.
    Causal exclusion arguments, especially as championed by Kim, have recently made life uncomfortable for would-be non-reductive physicalists. Non-reductive physicalism was itself, in turn, partly a response to earlier arguments against reductionism. The philosophy of science, though, distinguishes more forms of reduction than philosophy of mind generally cares to. In this paper I review four major families of reductionist thesis, and give reasons for keeping them more carefully separate than usual…Read more
  •  59
    Information processing and dynamical systems approaches are complementary
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 25 (5): 639-640. 2002.
    Shanker & King (S&K) trumpet the adoption of a “new paradigm” in communication studies, exemplified by ape language research. Though cautiously sympathetic, I maintain that their argument relies on a false dichotomy between “information” and “dynamical systems” theory, and that the resulting confusion prevents them from recognizing the main chance their line of thinking suggests.
  •  41
  •  39
    Why 'Appeals to Intuitions' might not be so bad
    South African Journal of Philosophy 29 (2): 156-166. 2010.
    There has been lively recent debate over the value of appeals to intuitions in philosophy. Some, especially ‘experimental philosophers’, have argued that such appeals can carry little or no evidential weight, and that standard analytic philosophy is consequently methodologically bankrupt. Various defences of intuitions, and analytic philosophy, have also been offered. In this paper I review the case against intuitions, in particular the claims that intuitions vary with culture, and are built by …Read more
  •  50
    Behavioral (pico)economics and the brain sciences
    with Don Ross
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28 (5): 659-660. 2005.
    Supporters of Ainslie's model face questions about its integration with neuroscience. Although processes of value estimation may well turn out to be locally implemented, methodological reasons suggest this is less likely in the case of subpersonal “interests.”.
  •  1582
    The completeness of physics
    Dissertation, University of Natal, Durban. 1999.
    The present work is focussed on the completeness of physics, or what is here called the Completeness Thesis: the claim that the domain of the physical is causally closed. Two major questions are tackled: How best is the Completeness Thesis to be formulated? What can be said in defence of the Completeness Thesis? My principal conclusions are that the Completeness Thesis can be coherently formulated, and that the evidence in favour if it significantly outweighs that against it. In opposition to th…Read more
  •  108
    Physicalism as an empirical hypothesis
    Synthese 194 (9): 3347-3360. 2017.
    Bas van Fraassen claims that materialism involves false consciousness. The thesis that matter is all that there is, he says, fails to rule out any kinds of theories. The false consciousness consists in taking materialism to be cognitive rather than an existential stance, or attitude, of deference to the current content of science in matters of ontology, and a favourable attitude to completeness claims about the content of science at a time. The main argument Van Fraassen provides for saying that…Read more
  •  405
    Does intragenomic conflict predict intrapersonal conflict?
    Biology and Philosophy 31 (3): 313-333. 2016.
    Parts of the genome of a single individual can have conflicting interests, depending on which parent they were inherited from. One mechanism by which these conflicts are expressed in some taxa, including mammals, is genomic imprinting, which modulates the level of expression of some genes depending on their parent of origin. Imprinted gene expression is known to affect body size, brain size, and the relative development of various tissues in mammals. A high fraction of imprinted gene expression …Read more
  •  106
    What Is Addiction? (edited book)
    with Don Ross and Harold Kincaid
    The MIT Press. 2010.
    Leading addiction researchers survey the latest findings in addiction science, countering the simplistic cultural stereotypes of the addict.
  •  974
    Notions of Cause: Russell’s Thesis Revisited
    with Don Ross
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (1): 45-76. 2007.
    We discuss Russell's 1913 essay arguing for the irrelevance of the idea of causation to science and its elimination from metaphysics as a precursor to contemporary philosophical naturalism. We show how Russell's application raises issues now receiving much attention in debates about the adequacy of such naturalism, in particular, problems related to the relationship between folk and scientific conceptual influences on metaphysics, and to the unification of a scientifically inspired worldview. In…Read more
  •  84
    Our point of departure is Russell’s (1913) argument for the ‘complete extrusion’ of the word ‘cause’ from the philosophical vocabulary. We argue that at least three different types of philosophical project concerning ‘cause’ should be carefully distinguished, and that failures to distinguish them lie at the root of some apparently recalcitrant problems. We call them the ‘cognitive’, the ‘scientific’ and the ‘metaphysical’.
  •  42
    Complexity and post-modernism: understanding complex systems
    with P. Cilliers
    South African Journal of Philosophy 18 (2): 258-274. 1999.
    This is a review article of Paul Cillier's 1999 book _Complexity and Postmodernism_. The review article is generally encouraging and constructive, although isolates a number of areas in need of clarification or development in Cillier's work. The volume of the _South African Journal of Philosophy_ in which the review article appeared also printed a response by Cilliers.
  •  4
    People differ in the extent to which they discount the values of future rewards. Behavioural economists measure these differences in terms of functions that describe rates of reduced valuation in the future – temporal discounting – as these vary with time. They measure differences in preference for risk – differing rates of probability discounting – in terms of similar functions that describe reduced valuation of rewards as the probability of their delivery falls. So-called ‘impulsive’ people, i…Read more
  •  58
    Jack Ritchie,Understanding Naturalism(Acumen, 2008)
    Philosophical Papers 40 (3): 439-445. 2011.
    Philosophical Papers, Volume 40, Issue 3, Page 439-445, November 2011
  •  62
    Bhaskar on Open and Closed Systems
    South African Journal of Philosophy 19 (3): 188-209. 2000.
    Bhaskar's articulation of his ‘transcendental realism' includes an argument for a form of causal emergence which would mean the rejection of physicalism, by means of rejecting the causal closure of the physical. His argument is based on an analysis of the conditions for closure, where closed systems manifest regular or Humean relations between events. Bhaskar argues that the project of seeking closure entails commitment to a strong reductionism, which in turn entails the impossibility of science…Read more
  •  74
    Why I am not an analytic philosopher
    South African Journal of Philosophy 27 (2): 153-163. 2008.
    From a certain simplistic and inaccurate, although regrettably popular, perspective philosophy, at least for the past few decades, is available only in two main flavours – analytic and continental. Some self-identified members of both camps are apt to endorse uncharitable caricatures of what the others are up to. Among the many lines of criticism that can be directed against this false dichotomy, I wish to focus on discussion of a broadly naturalistic orientation that rejects many of the commitm…Read more