•  58
    Jack Ritchie,Understanding Naturalism(Acumen, 2008)
    Philosophical Papers 40 (3): 439-445. 2011.
    Philosophical Papers, Volume 40, Issue 3, Page 439-445, November 2011
  •  62
    Bhaskar on Open and Closed Systems
    South African Journal of Philosophy 19 (3): 188-209. 2000.
    Bhaskar's articulation of his ‘transcendental realism' includes an argument for a form of causal emergence which would mean the rejection of physicalism, by means of rejecting the causal closure of the physical. His argument is based on an analysis of the conditions for closure, where closed systems manifest regular or Humean relations between events. Bhaskar argues that the project of seeking closure entails commitment to a strong reductionism, which in turn entails the impossibility of science…Read more
  • Causation in a structural world
    In James Ladyman & Don Ross (eds.), Every thing must go: metaphysics naturalized, Oxford University Press. 2007.
  •  74
    Why I am not an analytic philosopher
    South African Journal of Philosophy 27 (2): 153-163. 2008.
    From a certain simplistic and inaccurate, although regrettably popular, perspective philosophy, at least for the past few decades, is available only in two main flavours – analytic and continental. Some self-identified members of both camps are apt to endorse uncharitable caricatures of what the others are up to. Among the many lines of criticism that can be directed against this false dichotomy, I wish to focus on discussion of a broadly naturalistic orientation that rejects many of the commitm…Read more
  •  6
    Editorial
    with Deane-Peter Baker and Simon Beck
    South African Journal of Philosophy 23 (4). 2004.
  •  53
    This chapter applies the parity principle in discussing “active externalism,” which claims that the mind need not be confined within either the brain or body. Consequently, how one brain or body interacts with other brains and bodies must be explored, together with the problems that may arise out of this interaction. This chapter is not concerned with beliefs and desires as mental states but whether they play a role in controlling behavior. It argues the notion that any course of action consider…Read more
  •  41
    Putting infants in their place
    with Andrew Dellis
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (4): 524-525. 2004.
    The interests of mother and infants do not exactly coincide. Further, infants are not merely objects of attempted control by mothers, but the sources of attempts to control what mothers do. Taking account of the ways in which this is so suggests an enriched perspective on mother-infant interaction and on the beginnings of conventionalized signaling.
  •  53
    Hooray for babies
    South African Journal of Philosophy 30 (2): 197-206. 2011.
    David Benatar has argued that the coming into existence of a sentient being is always a harm, and consequently that people who have children always do wrong. The most natural objection maintains that in many lives (at least) while there is some pain, there are also goods (including pleasures) that can outweigh the suffering. From Benatar’s perspective this move, while possibly useful in assessing the lives of those who actually exist, is not an effective defence of procreation. In the case of pe…Read more
  •  300
    A wave of recent work in metaphysics seeks to undermine the anti-reductionist, functionalist consensus of the past few decades in cognitive science and philosophy of mind. That consensus apparently legitimated a focus on what systems do, without necessarily and always requiring attention to the details of how systems are constituted. The new metaphysical challenge contends that many states and processes referred to by functionalist cognitive scientists are epiphenomenal. It further contends that…Read more
  •  46
    An eye for an eye: Reciprocity and the calibration of redress
    with Andrew Dellis
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36 (1). 2013.
    General systems for reciprocity explain the same phenomena as the target article's proposed revenge system, and can explain other cooperative phenomena. We need more reason to hypothesise a specific revenge system. In addition, the proposed calculus of revenge is less sensitive to absolute magnitudes of revenge than it should be
  •  28
    “Very like a whale”: Analogies about the mind need salient similarity to convey information
    with Jeffrey Martin
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (4): 350-351. 2010.
    Knobe relies on unhelpful analogies in stating his main thesis about the mind. It isn't clear what saying the mind works, or doesn't work, or means. We suggest he should say that some think that human cognition respects a ban on fallacies of relevance, where considerations actually irrelevant to truth are taken as evidence. His research shows that no such ban is respected
  •  29
    Reason is normative, and should be studied accordingly
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 34 (5): 267-268. 2011.
    Reason aims at truth, so normative considerations are a proper part of the study of reasoning. Excluding them means neglecting some of what we know or can discover about reasoning. Also, the normativist position we are asked to reject by Elqayam & Evans (E&E) is defined in attenuated and self-contradictory ways
  •  21
    This paper is a critical, and fairly detailed, engagement with Lyotard's account of 'postmodern' science as it is found in his _The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge_.
  •  28
    Cui bono? Selfish goals need to pay their way
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 37 (2): 155-156. 2014.
  •  31
    Evolutionary psychology and functionally empty metaphors
    with Don Ross
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 29 (2): 192-193. 2006.
    Lea & Webley's (L&W's) non-exclusive distinction between tool-like and drug-like motivators is insufficiently discriminating to say much about money that is useful, as the distinction's equivocal application to sex, food, and drugs shows. Further, it appears as though the motivations of problem gamblers are non-metaphorically like those of drug addicts. (Published Online April 5 2006).
  •  298
    What physical properties are
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 82 (2): 201-225. 2001.
    This paper concerns the question of how to specify what is to count as physical for the purposes of debates concerning either physicalism or the completeness of physics. I argue that what is needed from an account of the physical depends primarily on the particular issue at stake, and that the demand for a general a priori specification of the physical is misplaced. A number of attempts to say what should be counted as physical are defended from recent attacks by Chris Daly, and a specific propo…Read more
  •  11
    Editorial
    with Deane-Peter Baker and Simon Beck
    South African Journal of Philosophy 24 (2): 61-63. 2005.
  •  176
    The Natural History of Desire
    South African Journal of Philosophy 34 (3): 304-313. 2015.
    Sterelny (2003) develops an idealised natural history of folk-psychological kinds. He argues that belief-like states are natural elaborations of simpler control systems, called detection systems, which map directly from environmental cue to response. Belief-like states exhibit robust tracking (sensitivity to multiple environmental states), and response breadth (occasioning a wider range of behaviours). The development of robust tracking and response-breadth depend partly on properties of the inf…Read more
  •  572
    A recurring claim in a number of behavioural, cognitive and neuro-scientific literatures is that there is, or must be, a unidimensional ‘common currency’ in which the values of different available options are represented. There is striking variety in the quantities or properties that have been proposed as determinants of the ordering in motivational strength. Among those seriously suggested are pain and pleasure, biological fitness, reward and reinforcement, and utility among economists, who hav…Read more
  •  422
    How to do things without words
    with S. J. Cowley
    Language Sciences 26 (5): 443-466. 2004.
    Clark and Chalmers (1998) defend the hypothesis of an ‘Extended Mind’, maintaining that beliefs and other paradigmatic mental states can be implemented outside the central nervous system or body. Aspects of the problem of ‘language acquisition’ are considered in the light of the extended mind hypothesis. Rather than ‘language’ as typically understood, the object of study is something called ‘utterance-activity’, a term of art intended to refer to the full range of kinetic and prosodic features o…Read more
  •  11
    Текущая сессия контакты копирайт
    South African Journal of Philosophy 18 (2): 258-274. 1999.
    I don't know what this document is. I'm not aware of ever being translated into Russian, but the issue and pagination suggest it refers to my review article of Cilliers' "Complexity and Postmodernism". That article is correctly indexed elsewhere on this site.
  •  50
    It's not just the subjects–there are too many WEIRD researchers
    with Michael Meadon
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 33 (2-3): 104-105. 2010.
    A literature in which most data are outliers is flawed, and the target article sounds a timely alarm call for the behavioural sciences. It also suggests remedies. We mostly concur, except for arguing that the importance of the fact that the researchers themselves are mostly outliers has been underplayed. Improving matters requires non-Western researchers, as well as research subjects
  •  62
    What about embodiment?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (5): 620-620. 2003.
    I present reasons for adding an embodiment criterion to the list defended by Anderson & Lebiere (A&L). I also entertain a likely objection contending that embodiment is merely a type of dynamic behavior and is therefore covered by the target article. In either case, it turns out that neither connectionism nor ACT-R do particularly well when it comes to embodiment.
  •  36
    Review of Burns, J. The Descent of Madness: Evolutionary Origins of Psychosis and the Social Brain (review)
    South African Journal of Philosophy 28 (2): 257-258. 2009.
    Review of Burns, J. The Descent of Madness: Evolutionary Origins of Psychosis and the Social Brain (London: Routledge, 2007)
  •  36
    Need there be a common currency for decision-making?
    South African Journal of Philosophy 28 (2): 210-221. 2009.
    According to various theorists and empirical scholars of behavior and decision, including economists, utility theorists, behavioral ecologists, behavioral economists and researchers in the new field of neuroeconomics the value (typically understood as utility) of competing choices must be represented on a common scale in order for them to count as competing at all, and in order for orderly comparison to lead to actual choices. For some neuroeconomists this means that expected (cardinal) utilitie…Read more
  •  612
    Cartwright on laws and composition
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15 (3). 2000.
    Cartwright attempts to argue from an analysis of the composition of forces, and more generally the composition of laws, to the conclusion that laws must be regarded as false. A response to Cartwright is developed which contends that properly understood composition poses no threat to the truth of laws, even though agreeing with Cartwright that laws do not satisfy the "facticity" requirement. My analysis draws especially on the work of Creary, Bhaskar, Mill, and points towards a general rejection …Read more
  •  4
  •  641
    What Physical Properties Are
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 82 (2): 201-225. 2001.
    This paper concerns the question of how to specify what is to count as physical for the purposes of debates concerning either physicalism or the completeness of physics. I argue that what is needed from an account of the physical depends primarily on the particular issue at stake, and that the demand for a general a priori specification of the physical is misplaced. A number of attempts to say what should be counted as physical are defended from recent attacks by Chris Daly, and a specific proposa…Read more
  •  36
    Editorial: New Developments at the SAJP
    with Deane-Peter Baker and Simon Beck
    South African Journal of Philosophy 25 (2): 89-90. 2006.
  •  19
    Transcendental realism defended: a response to Allan
    South African Journal of Philosophy 17 (3): 198-210. 1998.