•  40
    Some Surprising Implications of Negative Retributivism
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 31 (1): 49-62. 2013.
    Negative retributivism is the view that though the primary justifying aim of legal punishment is the reduction of crime, the state's efforts to do so are subject to side-constraints that forbid punishment of the innocent and disproportionate punishment of the guilty. I contend that insufficient attention has been paid to what the side-constraints commit us to in constructing a theory of legal punishment, even one primarily oriented toward reducing crime. Specifically, I argue that the side-const…Read more
  •  24
  •  46
    Social Deprivation as Tempting Fate
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 5 (3): 277-291. 2011.
    Two recent discussions concerning punishment of the socially deprived reach conflicting conclusions. Andrew von Hirsch and Andrew Ashworth argue that we should sympathize with the predicament of the poor and therefore mitigate their sentences. Peter Chau disputes von Hirsch and Ashworth’s conclusion, contending that having to face strong temptations is not an appropriate ground for reducing anyone’s punishment for their crimes. I argue that neither von Hirsch and Ashworth’s account nor Chau’s cr…Read more
  •  59
    Retributive parsimony
    Res Publica 15 (4): 377-395. 2009.
    Retributive approaches to the justification of legal punishment are often thought to place exacting and unattractive demands on state officials, requiring them to expend scarce public resources on apprehending and punishing all offenders strictly in accordance with their criminal ill deserts. Against this caricature of the theory, I argue that retributivists can urge parsimony in the use of punishment. After clarifying what parsimony consists in, I show how retributivists can urge reductions in …Read more
  •  29
    Remorse, Dialogue, and Sentencing
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 16 (3): 611-630. 2022.
    After surveying the many practical difficulties sentencing judges must confront in determining whether the offenders who appear before them are genuinely remorseful, recent dialogical accounts of remorse-based sentence reductions are examined. These accounts depend on a morally communicative approach to legal punishment’s justification and seem to confine such communication to offenders. They contend that, in order to respect remorseful offenders, sentencing judges must reduce their sentences. W…Read more
  •  75
    Preventive Pre-trial Detention without Punishment
    Res Publica 20 (2): 111-127. 2014.
    The pre-trial detention of individuals charged with crimes is viewed by many legal scholars as problematic. Standard arguments against it are that it constitutes legal punishment of individuals not yet convicted of crimes, violates the presumption of innocence, and rests on dubious predictions of future crime. I defend modified and restrained forms of pre-trial detention. I argue that pre-trial detention could be made very different than imprisonment, should be governed by strict criteria, and i…Read more
  •  5
    Five Concerns Regarding the Commercialization of Leisure
    Business and Society Review 106 (2): 107-126. 2001.
  •  36
    Those found liable for negligently injuring others are required to compensate them, but current practices permit most tort feasors to spread the costs of their liability burdens through the purchase of insurance. Those found guilty of criminal offences, however, are not allowed to shift the burdens of their sentences onto others. Yet the reasons for not allowing criminal offenders to shift such burdens – harm reduction, retribution, and moral education – also appear to retain some force in relat…Read more
  •  37
    Diminished Opportunities, Diminished Capacities
    Social Theory and Practice 29 (3): 459-485. 2003.
  •  28
    Chronic Temptation, Reasonable Firmness and the Criminal Law
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 34 (1): 75-96. 2014.
    The criminal law requires citizens to demonstrate ‘reasonable firmness’ in the face of temptations to violate its provisions. But what if individuals repeatedly face powerful temptations to offend, are not responsible for being in such predicaments, cannot escape them, and cannot alter or expunge their desires because they count as urgent on any plausible account of a decent human life? Should the criminal law make some sort of allowance for the chronically tempted? I argue that it should, becau…Read more
  •  104
    Advertising and the Social Conditions of Autonomy
    Business and Professional Ethics Journal 8 (4): 35-58. 1989.
  •  64
    A Critique of Business Ethics
    Business Ethics Quarterly 1 (4): 367-384. 1991.
    The dominant approach to the analysis of issues in business ethics consists in the articulation and use of a set of mid-level moral principles. This approach is geared to business practitioners who are not interested in the difficult problems of moral and political theory. I argue that this "practitioner model" is philosophically suspect. I show how the theoretical frameworks prominent business ethicists employ are insufficiently developed. I also show how many of their analyses presuppose subst…Read more
  •  52
    Justice and Insider Trading
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 10 (2): 215-226. 1993.
    While many countries are following the lead of the United States in making insider trading illegal, its moral status is still controversial. I summarise the scholarly debate over the fairness of insider trading and lay bare the assumptions about fairness implicit in that debate. I focus on the question whether those assumptions can be defended independently of a more comprehensive theory of social justice. Current analyses presuppose that we can intelligently discuss what the social rules regard…Read more
  •  68
    To Waive or Not to Waive: The Right to Trial and Plea Bargaining (review)
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 2 (2): 181-199. 2008.
    Criminal defendants in many countries are faced with a dilemma: If they waive their right to trial and plead guilty, they typically receive charge or sentence reductions in exchange for having done so. If they exercise their right to trial and are found guilty, they often receive stiffer sanctions than if they had pled guilty. I characterize the former as ‘waiver rewards’ and the latter as ‘non-waiver penalties.’ After clarifying the two and considering the relation between them, I briefly expli…Read more
  •  20
    Punishment, Public Safety, and Collateral Legal Consequences
    Journal of Applied Philosophy. forthcoming.
    What are termed the ‘collateral legal consequences’ (or CLCs) of criminal conviction have been defended in a variety of ways. The focus in this article is on efforts to justify the burdens and restrictions they involve as nonpenal measures designed to secure public safety. Zachary Hoskins' careful defense of such public‐safety CLCs is utilized as a point of departure. Although it is granted that such measures might be defensible, the many complications and problems of ensuring that they do not a…Read more
  • Imprisonable offenses
    In Thom Brooks (ed.), Law and Legal Theory, Brill. 2013.
  •  35
    Retributivism and Victim Compensation
    Social Theory and Practice 46 (2): 317-338. 2020.
    Given the desert-centric character of retributive penal theory, it seems odd that its supporters rarely discuss the undeserved losses and suffering of crime victims and the state’s role in responding to them. This asymmetry in the desert-focus of retributive penal theory is examined and the likely arguments in support of it are found wanting. Particular attention is paid to the claim that offenders, rather than the state, should supply compensation to victims. Also, standard retributive accounts…Read more
  •  29
    Two Ways of Thinking About the Value of Deserved Punishment
    The Journal of Ethics 23 (4): 387-406. 2019.
    Numerous retributivists hold that deserved punishment has intrinsic value. A number of puzzles regarding that claim are identified and discussed. An alternative, more Kantian account of intrinsic value is then identified and the ways in which legal punishment might be understood to cohere with it are explored. That account focuses on the various ways in which legal punishment might be persons-respecting. It is then argued that this Kantian account enables us to solve or evade the puzzles generat…Read more
  •  24
    Legal Punishment and the Public Identification of Offenders
    Res Publica 24 (2): 199-216. 2018.
    In the United States, the identities of criminal offenders are matters of public record, accessible to prospective employers, the press, and ordinary citizens. In European countries, the identities of offenders are routinely kept hidden, with some exceptions. The question addressed in this discussion concerns whether the public disclosure of the identities of offenders is part and parcel of their legal punishment. My contentions are that public disclosure is not conceptually part of legal punish…Read more
  •  46
    The Nature of Retributive Justice and Its Demands on the State
    Law and Philosophy 38 (1): 53-77. 2019.
    The enterprise of state punishment requires the use of limited resources for which there are other competitors, such as national defense, market regulation, and social welfare. How resource-demanding retributive justice will turn out to be depends on how retributivists answer a series of questions concerning the theory’s structure. After elaborating these questions and the varieties of retributive justice that answers to them might generate, I consider the resource demands of retributive justice…Read more
  •  155
    Punishing the Guilty, Not Punishing the Innocent
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 7 (4): 462-488. 2010.
    Discussion in this paper focuses on how strongly we should prefer non-punishment of persons guilty of serious crimes to punishment of persons innocent of them. William Blackstone's version of that preference, expressed as a ten to one ratio, is first shown to be untenable on standard accounts of legal punishment's justifying aims. Somewhat weaker versions of that ratio also appear suspect. More to the point, Blackstone's adage obscures the crucial way in which there are risks to be assessed in s…Read more
  •  73
    Imprisonable offenses
    Journal of Moral Philosophy 3 (3): 265-287. 2006.
    Imprisonment imposes very substantial losses and deprivations on people convicted of crimes. The question for which crimes imprisonment is an appropriate sanction is addressed employing both retributive and crime reduction approaches to the justification of legal punishment. Although there is not complete convergence between what the two approaches imply about its use, it is argued that both would reserve imprisonment for serious offenses, ones that inflict or threaten significant harms with mod…Read more
  •  18
    The Disenfranchisement of Felons
    Law and Philosophy 20 (6): 553-580. 2001.
    After discussing the interests that ground theright to democratic political participation,arguments for the disenfranchisement of thosewho commit serious criminal offenses areexamined. The arguments are divided into twogroups. The first group consists of argumentsthat are relatively independent of thejustifying aims of punishment. It is concededthat two of these arguments establish thatsome, though by no means all, serious offendersshould lose the vote for a period of time thatdoes not necessari…Read more
  •  28
    Speech, Conscience, and Work
    Social Theory and Practice 18 (3): 237-258. 1992.
  •  57
    Retributivism and Plea Bargaining
    Criminal Justice Ethics 25 (2): 3-16. 2006.