•  634
    A Very British Hobbes, or A More European Hobbes?
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 22 (2): 368-386. 2014.
    Malcolm’s English-Latin Leviathan is a marvelous technical accomplishment. My issues are with his contextualization, seeing Leviathan primarily as an advice book for Hobbes’s teenage pupil, the future Charles II. Malcolm’s localization involves minimalizing Leviathan's remoter sources, so the European Republic of Letters, for which Hobbes so painstakingly translated his works into Latin, is almost entirely missing, along with current European traditions of Hobbes scholarship. Is this very Briti…Read more
  •  37
    The duck/rabbit Hobbes
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 14 (4). 2006.
    Once in a blue moon a book comes along capable of effecting a Gestalt Switch and Jeffrey Collin’s The Allegiance of Thomas Hobbes is just such a book. Here we have the duck/rabbit Hobbes, so long seen as an unmitigated Royalist, now exposed as an ardent Cromwellian.
  •  991
    Karl Marx on Democracy, Participation, Voting, and Equality
    Political Theory 12 (4): 537-556. 1984.
    Marx's Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right (1843) makes the very case for Democracy as a privileged constitutional form that he makes in the 1844 Manuscripts for communism. Democracy is the "generic constitution" to which monarchy stands as a species. Democracy is "content and form", since the state is essentially the Demos and Democracy is goverment of the People. "Democracy is the resolved mystery of all constitutions".
  •  1661
    Hobbes’s materialism and Epicurean mechanism
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 24 (5): 814-835. 2016.
    ABSTRACT: Hobbes belonged to philosophical and scientific circles grappling with the big question at the dawn of modern physics: materialism and its consequences for morality. ‘Matter in motion’ may be a core principle of this materialism but it is certainly inadequate to capture the whole project. In wave after wave of this debate the Epicurean view of a fully determined universe governed by natural laws, that nevertheless allows to humans a sphere of libertas, but does not require a creator go…Read more
  • David Runciman: Pluralism and the Personality of the State
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 7 (1): 162-164. 1999.
  •  406
    Aristotle and the Problem of Needs
    History of Political Thought 5 (3): 393-424. 1984.
    "Justice according to Need" is an old socialist slogan and Marxism embraced an ancient theory of true and false needs. But Aristotle also formulated "justice according to need", although in different terms, where "need" is often translated as "demand".
  •  287
    The Paradoxical Hobbes
    Political Theory 37 (5): 676-688. 2009.
    Attention has turned from Hobbes the systematic thinker to his inconsistencies, as the essays in the Hobbes symposium published in the recent volume of Political Theory suggest. Deborah Baumgold, in “The Difficulties of Hobbes Interpretation,” shifted the focus to “the history of the book,” and Hobbes’s method of serial composition and peripatetic insertion, as a major source of his inconsistency. Accepting Baumgold’s method, the author argues that the manner of composition does not necessarily …Read more
  •  14
    Review article: the view from the 'divell's mountain'
    History of Political Thought 17 (4): 615-622. 1996.
    Quentin Skinner, Reason and Rhetoric in The Philosophy of Hobbes , xvi + 477 pp., ?35.00, ISBN 0 521 55436 5
  •  1373
    Hobbes o religiji
    Problemi 3. 1997.
    ABSTRACT: Why would someone concerned with heresy, who defined it as private opinion that flew in the face of doctrine sanctioned by the public person, harbor such a detailed interest in heterodoxy? Hobbes's religious beliefs ultimately remain a mystery, as perhaps they were meant to: the private views of someone concerned to conform outwardly to what his church required of him, and thereby avoid to heresy, while maintaining intellectual autonomy. The hazard of Hobbes's particular catechism is t…Read more
  •  113
    Among the paradoxical aspects of Hobbes's scepticism attention has recently turned to Hobbes's fool of Leviathan , chapter xv, where Hobbes makes a claim about justice that paraphrases Psalm 52:1: "The fool hath said in his heart there is no God." It is a charge of which Hobbes himself could be suspected, but in fact we see that it is on this startling claim that his legal positivism rests. Moreover it is embedded in a theory of natural law that Hobbes inherited from the late scholastics and tha…Read more
  •  182
    Behemoth'and Hobbes's" science of just and unjust
    Filozofski Vestnik 24 (2): 267-289. 2003.
    This essay advances the following set of arguments: First, that we must take seriously Hobbes's claim in Behemoth that "the science of just & unjust" is a demonstrable science, accessible to those of even the meanest capacity. Second, that Leviathan is the work in which this science, intended as a serious project in civic education, is set out. Third, that Hobbes is prepared to accept, like Plato & Aristotle, "giving to each his own," as a preliminary definition of justice, from which however, h…Read more
  •  685
    Hobbes's Challenge to Descartes, Bramhall and Boyle: A Corporeal God
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 20 (5): 903-934. 2012.
    This paper brings new work to bear on the perennial question about Hobbes's atheism to show that as a debate about scepticism it is falsely framed. Hobbes, like fellow members of the Mersenne circle, Descartes and Gassendi, was no sceptic, but rather concerned to rescue physics and metaphysics from radical scepticism by exploring corporealism. In his early letter of November 1640, Hobbes had issued a provocative challenge to Descartes to abandon metaphysical dualism and subscribe to a ?corporeal…Read more
  •  34
    The enlightenment of Thomas Hobbes
    British Journal for the History of Philosophy 12 (3). 2004.
    No abstract