•  280
    Paul Ricoeur, Linguaggio e filosofia (review)
    Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 88 (3). 1996.
    A review of a collection of papers by Paul Ricoeur edited by Domenico Jervolino. The collection highlights Ricoeur's journey from the reflexive philosophy to analytic philosophy through hermeneutics
  •  137
    Jurgen Habermas, Fatti e norme (review)
    Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 91 (1): 142-150. 1999.
    The evolution of Habermas follows that of Rawls in Political Liberalism, where the principles of justice are traced back to a historical background and no longer derived from an original position as in A Theory of Justice; and even Rawls, curiously enough, while he made his own the criticism in a broad sense Hegelian, of opponents such as Walzer,continued not to recognize the debt he now owed them. Appropriations of the opponents' objections, withdrawals disguised as victories, ad hoc distincti…Read more
  •  218
    Stuart Newton Hampshire, Innocenza e esperienza. Un'etica del conflitto (review)
    Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 88 (1): 174-175. 1996.
    Hampshire addresses the problem of pluralism, i.e. conflicts, characteristic of modern societies, which arise from the presence of conflicting moral interests and duties. The solution is a procedural notion of justice, seen as the precondition for respect for the different positive conceptions of the good. A salient feature of the book is the combination of a form of a 'weak' Aristotelianism, similar to that of Bernard Williams and far away from that of MacIntyre, with the theme of the relations…Read more
  •  579
    Sidgwick, Henry, I metodi dell'etica, ed. by Maurizio Mori. (review)
    Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 88 (1): 175-176. 1996.
    A short presentation of the first Italian translation of a classic of Modern Ethics ignored by Italian philosophers for more than a century
  •  181
    Cristina Marras, Metaphora translata voce (review)
    Rivista di Filosofia 101 (3): 450-452. 2010.
    The theses in this book are: 1) the tension between the Leibnizian theory of the tropes and their use is resolved in a "pragmatic of discourse" that gives the metaphor a richer dimension than the theorized one, that is, that of "a mechanism capable of combining elements coming from different conceptual spaces into a new metaphorical conceptual space, 'shapeless' to which the metaphor itself provides an adequate language to describe and structure it"; 2) the role of metaphors is placed for Leibn…Read more
  •  171
    L Dumont, 'From Mandeville to Marx' (review)
    Rivista Internazionale di Scienze Sociali 89 (2): 743-748. 1980.
    Alongside the aspects of interest in the history of ideas in general, this text is of great interest to the economist and the philosopher of economics. The parts on Smith and Marx are a demonstration of how it is possible to make a history of scientific thought that explains the incongruities of the history of thought in front of which Schumpeter stops: these incongruities cease to be mysterious, and indeed they acquire full meaning if we accept the idea of considering in scientific texts not on…Read more
  •  234
    Il dolore, la speranza, il paradosso (review)
    Il Mulino 36 (5): 837-842. 1987.
    The malaise of modernity, in particular the malaise diagnosed by Nietzsche in the face of the absurdity of suffering, stems from an unfinished, dogmatic and contradictory revival of elements that medieval synthesis had marginalised: hope and earthliness. The ideologies of modernity - revolutionary-progressive or technical - were condemned to be ideologies, and therefore dogmatic, because they were based on faiths smuggled as reasons. Today we live a moment of awareness of the unfinished characte…Read more
  •  149
    J.J.E. Gracia, E. Rabossi, E. Villanueva, M. Dascal (eds), 'El análisis filosófico en América Latina' (review)
    Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 80 (2): 314-317. 1988.
    The definition of "philosophical analysis" is far from obvious and the definition adopted by the editors should be mentioned. The editors wish to designate with this term, as is often done in the English-speaking world, a much broader tradition than that of "analytical philosophy", one initiated by the disciples of the second Wittgenstein and including Moore, Russell, Wittgenstein, the Vienna Circle, neo-empiricism and the "philosophy of ordinary language". From the editors' introductions it is…Read more
  •  154
    A Cohen & M Dascal (eds), 'The Institution of Philosophy' (review)
    Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 86 (3): 609-613. 1994.
    A review of a collection of essays one meta-philosophy by fifteen philosophers, including Rorty, Castañeda and Putnam. It is a stimulating collection, useful reading for those who want to go beyond the caricatures of today's philosophy in America, for those interested in the discussion on the origins of the split between continental philosophy and Anglo-American philosophy and for the philosopher who does not disdain a moment of "self-consciousness". The editors, both teaching at Tel-Aviv Univer…Read more
  •  682
    By reconstructing the eighteenth-century movement of the Italian Enlightenment, I show that Italy’s political fragmentation notwithstanding, there was a constant circulation of ideas, whether on philosophical, ethical, political, religious, social, economic or scientific questions—among different groups in various states. This exchange was made possible by the shared language of its leading illuministi— Cesare Beccaria, Ludovico Antonio Muratori, Francesco Maria Zanotti, Antonio Genovesi, Mario …Read more
  •  516
    John Rawls, Liberalismo politico (review)
    Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 87 (4). 1995.
    One of the points of interest of A Theory of Justice was that it tied so tightly together efficiency and equity; however, this link was entrusted to the "principle of difference" and the related maximin rule, the very point that is dropped in this book. Now society as a cooperative enterprise becomes part of the shared concept of the just society and it is no longer the reason for its justification; on this basis, however, Rawls lucidly asks the question about the justification for solidarity w…Read more
  •  172
    Ronna Burger, Aristotle’s Dialogue with Socrates (review)
    Rivista di Filosofia 101 (1): 119-120. 2010.
    In order to understand the Gricean "logic of conversation" that underlies the Nicomachean Ethics, Burger believes it necessary to identify the audience to which the work is addressed: this is the audience of men and citizens who have received a good education, that is, have learned the virtues through habit, but have doubts about the content of the education received, that is, about the beautiful and the just. Aristotle proposes on the one hand to give them reasons to defend and justify the mora…Read more
  •  222
    F Amerini, Tommaso d’Aquino. Origine e fine della vita umana (review)
    Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 102 (4): 716-718. 2010.
    Amerini declares that by this book he did not want to make any contribution to the contemporary bioethical debate, or in another way, he wanted to give a preliminary contribution of great importance. His opinion on the implications of Aquinas's embryological theory for today's bioethical debate is in fact that it "certainly has some bioethical consequences, but it does not give rise to one particular bioethical theory rather than another. It is, as said, a philosophical explanation, traced in te…Read more
  •  175
    M Milgate & SC Stimson, Ricardian Politics (review)
    European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 1 (3): 642-643. 1994.
    The book is quite convincing as far as it argues more autonomy from Mill and a more pro-working-class picture than the received image of Ricardo allows for. A severe pitfall is having ignored the relevance of Unitarianism as a matrix of political radicalism. A related defect is not having exploited less obvious sources than those included in Sraffa’s edition.
  •  122
    A Pandolfi, Généalogie et dialectique de la raison mercantiliste (review)
    European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 6 (4): 644-645. 1999.
    I argue that the word mercantilism, born in the beginning from a nasty rhetorical move by Adam Smith, still preserves so much evocative power as to be used emblematically as a name for a whole historical period because of its natural use as a label for aggressive and unfair economic policies but, for analytic purposes we should bring to an end cross-purpose talk between historians of ideas and historians of society.
  •  198
    S Rashid, The Myth of Adam Smith (review)
    European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 6 (1): 314-316. 1999.
    My objections are: first, we may ask whether the achievement of The Wealth of Nations has been that of creating a new and more encompassing conceptual framework where already existing theoretical elements could be integrated and whether the growth of knowledge could have originated from a growth in the consistency of a theoretical framework which synthesized already existing individual elements; secondly, we may ask whether Smith's "tendentious" presentation of the positions of both predecessors…Read more
  •  167
    R Calderón Cuadrado, Armonía de interéses y modernidad. Radicales del pensamiento económico (review)
    European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 6 (4): 652-653. 1999.
    I suggest that the image of Adam Smith suffers from an emphasis on the role of “utilitarian calculus”, besides on overlooking the role of a “Stoic” point of view from which vanity, selfishness, and even enlightened self-interest are ultimately valueless, and finally a restricted view of prudence.
  •  201
    N Sigot, Bentham et l'économie (review)
    European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 10 (1): 167-172. 2003.
    I discuss the interpretation of the principle of utility as a factual statement, the relevance of Halévy's interetation of Bentham, and then Bentham's relationship with James Mill and David Ricardo.
  •  225
    JB Davis, The Theory of the Individual in Economics. Identity and Value (review)
    History of Economic Ideas 12 (3): 125-129. 2004.
    I argue that Adam Smith does more than providing an account of competitive behavior loosely linked to an underlying psychology since the joint between the complex psychology of The Theory of Moral Sentiments and the invisible hand pages in The Wealth of Nations explains why some of the basest affections, greed and ambition, prevail over other tendencies in certain social groups, namely merchants and manufacturers, in a commercial and urban society.
  •  199
    GEM Anscombe, Faith in a Hard Ground: Essays on Religion, Philosophy and Ethics (review)
    Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 101 (4): 587-590. 2009.
    I discuss this collection of published and unpublished essays on religion and ethics by GEM Anscombe edited by Mary Geach and Luke Gormally. My main doubt concerns the criteria on which papers have been included in this volume. I argue that, while part of the material included typically belongs to a discussion between believers, some of these are good examples of applied ethics with no direct link with the Christian faith and addressed to a universal audience of reasonable partners of conversati…Read more
  •  301
    Review of Ch.M.A. Clark, Economic Theory and Natural Philosophy. (review)
    European Journal of the History of Economic Thought 1 (2): 356-359. 1990.
    A review of Ch.M.A. Clark, Economic Theory and Natural Philosophy. The Search for the Natural Laws of the Economy. The key point of my critical appraisal is lack of univocal definition of nature, natural law and natural philosophy.
  •  237
    Review of D. Wilson and W. Dixon, A History of Homo Economicus (review)
    History of Economic Ideas 19 (3): 224-227. 2012.
    A critical discussion of DAVID WILSON and WILLIAM DIXON, A History of Homo Economicus. The nature of the moral in economic theory, London and New York, Routledge, pp. xviii+123 ISBN 978-0-415-59568-1. I declare agreement with one basic idea in this book, that economic discourse is performative, or economic theory is not pure theorìa. I add several objections to the historical reconstruction carried out os such authors as Malthus and Ricardo and I object to the definition adopted of homo econo…Read more
  •  233
    A discussion of a collection of essays by French scholars on Adam Smith, mainly but not exclusively, on his political theory.
  •  171
    Review of Carsten Herrmann-Pillath, Foundations of Economic Evolution (review)
    Journal of the History of Economic Thought 38 (1). 2015.
    A review of Carsten Herrmann-Pillath, Foundations of Economic Evolution. A Treatise on the Natural Philosophy of Economics. I argue that the author's ultra-naturalist stance in epistemology lacks consistent justification
  •  372
    Metafore, modelli, linguaggio scientifico: il dibattito postempirista
    In Virgilio Melchiorre (ed.), Simbolo e conoscenza, Vita E Pensiero. pp. 31-102. 1988.
    I discuss Mary Hess’s interaction-view of scientific metaphor, outline an alternative view and show how it may prove fruitful when applied to chapters of the history of science. I start with a reconstruction of the discussion on the nature of scientific models and on their relationship to metaphors that has taken place in the Anglo-Saxon philosophy of Science starting from the Fifties; the discovery started with Stephen Pepper and Kenneth Burke, reaching Thomas Kuhn, Marx Wartofsky, and George…Read more
  •  1751
    La teoria dei sentimenti morali (review)
    Philosophy and Public Issues - Filosofia E Questioni Pubbliche 3 (1): 199-206. 1996.
    A discussion of the Italian edition of Adam Smith's moral work edited by Eugenio Lecaldano.
  •  282
    Review of Judith P. Butler 'Subjects of Desire. Hegelian Reflections in Twentieth-century France' (review)
    Rivista di Filosofia Neo-Scolastica 82 (1): 174-175. 1990.
    A review of Butler's first book. An English version has been posted.
  •  192
    Merchants, Master-Manufacturers and Greedy People (review)
    History of Economic Ideas 15 (2): 143-154. 2007.
    A discussion of McCloskey's argument for bourgeois virtue ethics in 'Bourgeois Virtues'. I criticise the opposition of Adam Smith's and Kant's ethics, arguing that Kant and Smith share much more than the author believes. I criticise the idea that what is most respectable in modern liberal-democratic societies is a gift of Capitalism, arguing that it is a gift of movements, associations, networks, and religious communities that strenuously resisted for a couple of centuries to 'Capitalism'.