•  3
    Synthetic Biology for Human Health: Issues for Ethical Discussion and Policy‐making
    with Nikola Biller-Andorno and Ruud ter Meulen
    Bioethics 27 (8). 2013.
  •  25
    “Who is watching the watchdog?”: ethical perspectives of sharing health-related data for precision medicine in Singapore
    with Tamra Lysaght, Angela Ballantyne, Vicki Xafis, Serene Ong, Gerald Owen Schaefer, Jeffrey Min Than Ling, Ing Wei Khor, and E. Shyong Tai
    BMC Medical Ethics 21 (1): 1-11. 2020.
    Background We aimed to examine the ethical concerns Singaporeans have about sharing health-data for precision medicine and identify suggestions for governance strategies. Just as Asian genomes are under-represented in PM, the views of Asian populations about the risks and benefits of data sharing are under-represented in prior attitudinal research. Methods We conducted seven focus groups with 62 participants in Singapore from May to July 2019. They were conducted in three languages and analysed …Read more
  •  36
    Clinical ethics committees (CECs) in the United Kingdom (UK) have developed significantly over the past 15 years. The issue of access to and participation in clinical ethics consultation by patients and family members has, however, gone largely unrecognized. There are various dimensions to this kind of contact, including patient notification, consent and participation. This study reports the first specific investigation of patient contact with UK CECs. A questionnaire study was carried out with …Read more
  •  45
    Clinical ethics consultation in Europe: a comparative and ethical review of the role of patients
    with Véronique Fournier, Eirini Rari, Reidun Førde, Gerald Neitzke, and Renzo Pegoraro
    Clinical Ethics 4 (3): 131-138. 2009.
    Clinical ethics has developed significantly in Europe over the past 15 years and remains an evolving process. While sharing our experiences in different European settings, we were surprised to discover marked differences in our practice, especially regarding the position and role of patients. In this paper, we describe these differences, such as patient access to and participation or representation in ethics consults. We propose reasons to explain these differences, hypothesizing that they relat…Read more
  •  67
    The role of patients in European clinical ethics consultation
    with Gerald Neitzke and Stella Reiter-Theil
    Clinical Ethics 4 (3): 109-110. 2009.
  •  24
    Ethical considerations for choosing between possible models for using NIPD for aneuploidy detection
    with Zuzana Deans
    Journal of Medical Ethics 38 (10): 614-618. 2012.
    Recent scientific advances mean the widespread introduction of non-invasive prenatal diagnosis (NIPD) for chromosomal aneuploidies may be close at hand, raising the question of how NIPD should be introduced as part of antenatal care pathways for pregnant women. In this paper, the authors examine the ethical implications of three hypothetical models for using NIPD for aneuploidy in state-funded healthcare systems and assess which model is ethically preferable. In comparing the models, the authors…Read more
  •  12
    The law often calls on the concept of public interest for assistance. Privacy law makes use of this concept in several ways, including to justify consent waivers for secondary research on health information. Because the law sees information privacy as a means for individuals to control their personal information, consent can only be set aside in special circumstances. Ballantyne and Schaefer argue that only public interest, and only a broad conception of public interest, can do the special ‘norm…Read more
  •  19
    ‘There is a lot of good in knowing, but there is also a lot of downs’: public views on ethical considerations in population genomic screening
    with Amelia K. Smit, Gillian Reyes-Marcelino, Louise Keogh, and Anne E. Cust
    Journal of Medical Ethics 47 (12). 2021.
    Publics are key stakeholders in population genomic screening and their perspectives on ethical considerations are relevant to programme design and policy making. Using semi-structured interviews, we explored social views and attitudes towards possible future provision of personalised genomic risk information to populations to inform prevention and/or early detection of relevant conditions. Participants were members of the public who had received information on their personal genomic risk of mela…Read more
  •  14
    Disclosure to genetic relatives without consent – Australian genetic professionals’ awareness of the health privacy law
    with Jane Fleming, Kate Dunlop, Kristine Barlow-Stewart, and Natalia Meggiolaro
    BMC Medical Ethics 21 (1): 1-10. 2020.
    Background: When a genetic mutation is identified in a family member, internationally, it is usually the proband’s or another responsible family member’s role to disclose the information to at-risk relatives. However, both active and passive non-disclosure in families occurs: choosing not to communicate the information or failing to communicate the information despite intention to do so, respectively. The ethical obligations to prevent harm to at-risk relatives and promote the duty of care by ge…Read more
  •  29
    From Expectations to Experiences: Consumer Autonomy and Choice in Personal Genomic Testing
    with Jacqueline Savard, Chriselle Hickerton, Sylvia A. Metcalfe, Clara Gaff, and Anna Middleton
    AJOB Empirical Bioethics 11 (1): 63-76. 2020.
    Background: Personal genomic testing (PGT) offers individuals genetic information about relationships, wellness, sporting ability, and health. PGT is increasingly accessible online, including in emerging markets such as Australia. Little is known about what consumers expect from these tests and whether their reflections on testing resonate with bioethics concepts such as autonomy. Methods: We report findings from focus groups and semi-structured interviews that explored attitudes to and experien…Read more
  •  66
    Artificial gametes: new paths to parenthood?
    Journal of Medical Ethics 31 (3): 184-186. 2005.
    A number of recent papers have described the successful derivation of egg and sperm precursor cells from mouse embryonic stem cells—so-called “artificial” gametes. Although many scientific questions remain, this research suggests numerous new possibilities for stem cell research and assisted reproductive technology, if a similar breakthrough is achieved with human embryonic stem cells. The novel opportunities raised by artificial gametes also prompt new ethical questions, such as whether same-se…Read more
  •  10
    Personal Genomics as an Interactive Web Broadcast
    American Journal of Bioethics 9 (6-7): 27-29. 2009.
    No abstract
  •  31
    Should Parental Refusals of Newborn Screening Be Respected?
    Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 15 (2): 135-146. 2006.
    For over four decades, knowledge that symptoms of some inherited diseases can be prevented or reduced via early detection and treatment in newborns has underpinned state-funded screening programs in most developed countries. Conditions for which newborn screening is now a recognized preventative public health initiative include phenylketonuria, congenital hypothyroidism, and, more recently, cystic fibrosis and sickle cell disorder. The use of tandem mass spectrometry to detect conditions such as…Read more
  •  30
    Whither authenticity?
    American Journal of Bioethics 5 (3). 2005.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  32
    Clinical genetics and the problem with unqualified confidentiality
    with Rony E. Duncan
    American Journal of Bioethics 6 (2). 2006.
    No abstract
  •  62
    Behavioural Genetics: Why Eugenic Selection is Preferable to Enhancement
    with Julian Savulescu, Melanie Hemsley, and Bennett Foddy
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 23 (2): 157-171. 2006.
    Criminal behaviour is but one behavioural tendency for which a genetic influence has been suggested. Whilst this research certainly raises difficult ethical questions and is subject to scientific criticism, one recent research project suggests that for some families, criminal tendency might be predicted by genetics. In this paper, supposing this research is valid, we consider whether intervening in the criminal tendency of future children is ethically justifiable. We argue that, if avoidance of …Read more
  •  31
    Should We Undertake Genetic Research on Intelligence?
    with Robert Williamson
    Bioethics 13 (3-4): 327-342. 1999.
    Although the concept of intelligence is difficult to define, research has provided evidence for a significant genetic component. Attempts are now being made to use molecular genetic approaches to identify genes contributing to intelligence, and to determine the ways in which they interact with environmental variables. This research is then likely to determine the developmental pathways of intelligence, in an effort to understand mental handicap and learning disorders and develop new treatment st…Read more
  •  77
    The nature and significance of behavioural genetic information
    Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 25 (2): 89-111. 2004.
    In light of the human genome project, establishing the genetic aetiology of complex human diseases has become a research priority within Western medicine. However, in addition to the identification of disease genes, numerous research projects are also being undertaken to identify genes contributing to the development of human behavioural characteristics, such as cognitive ability and criminal tendency. The permissibility of this research is obviously controversial: will society benefit from this…Read more
  •  45
    Communication of genetic information within families: The case for familial comity (review)
    with Angela Davey and Peter O’Leary
    Journal of Bioethical Inquiry 3 (3): 161-166. 2006.
    Advances in genetic technologies raise a multitude of ethical issues, some of which give rise to novel dilemmas for medical practice. One of the most controversial problems arising in clinical genetics is that of confidentiality and who may disclose genetic health information. This paper considers the question of when it is appropriate for health professionals to disclose clinically significant genetic information without patient consent. Existing ethical principles offer little guidance in rela…Read more
  •  27
    This target article considers the ethical implications of providing prenatal diagnosis and antenatal screening services to detect fetal abnormalities in jurisdictions that prohibit abortion for these conditions. This unusual health policy context is common in the Latin American region. Congenital conditions are often untreated or under-treated in developing countries due to limited health resources, leading many women/couples to prefer termination of affected pregnancies. Three potential harms d…Read more
  •  32
    Rethinking Pediatric Ethics Consultations
    with Henry Kilham, David Isaacs, and Ian Kerridge
    American Journal of Bioethics 15 (5): 26-28. 2015.
    Johnson and colleagues (2015) report a retrospective review of the experience of an ethics consultation service at a single, highly specialized children's hospital over an 11-year period. Despite i...
  •  47
    Prenatal Diagnosis and Abortion for Congenital Abnormalities: Is It Ethical to Provide One Without the Other?
    with Angela Ballantyne, Florencia Luna, and Richard Ashcroft
    American Journal of Bioethics 9 (8): 48-56. 2009.
    This target article considers the ethical implications of providing prenatal diagnosis (PND) and antenatal screening services to detect fetal abnormalities in jurisdictions that prohibit abortion for these conditions. This unusual health policy context is common in the Latin American region. Congenital conditions are often untreated or under-treated in developing countries due to limited health resources, leading many women/couples to prefer termination of affected pregnancies. Three potential h…Read more