Joseph Agassi

York University
D'Annunzio University of Chieti–Pescara
  • Technology, Philosophical and Social Aspects
    Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 18 (1): 322-331. 1987.
  •  18
    The novelty of Chomsky's theories
    In David Martel Johnson & Christina E. Erneling (eds.), The Future of the Cognitive Revolution, Oxford University Press. pp. 136--148. 1997.
  •  12
  •  78
    The mystery of the ravens
    Philosophy of Science 33 (4): 395-402. 1966.
  •  25
    The Manhattan Project and Its Long Shadow
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 41 (4): 574-595. 2011.
    A sequel to Shapin’s earlier work, The Scientific Life: A Moral History of a Late Modern Vocation again solves the problem of induction by observing that researchers are decent. Shapin dismisses most of the literature on both the philosophy of science and (more so) on the sociology of science as ideologically biased and as irrelevant. Approaches to the book as light reading and as serious scholarly reading are considered before a critical summary is offered as a conclusion
  •  19
    This Message is for You. Maybe
    Philosophy and Literature 7 (1): 95-98. 1983.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:THIS MESSAGE IS FOR YOU. MAYBE. by Joseph Agassi There is a mood often enough conjured in science fiction literature to be familiar to every fan, the mood of seemingly intentional yet probably remdom contact between two individuals across immense space-time expanses. The hero of a complicated chase story has lost contact with the mother planet, has long ago leuided on a strange pleuiet, emd there, right now, just walking across the p…Read more
  •  15
    The Manhattan Project and Its Long Shadow (review)
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 41 (4): 574-595. 2011.
    A sequel to Shapin’s earlier work, The Scientific Life: A Moral History of a Late Modern Vocation again solves the problem of induction by observing that researchers are decent. Shapin dismisses most of the literature on both the philosophy of science and (more so) on the sociology of science as ideologically biased and as irrelevant. Approaches to the book as light reading and as serious scholarly reading are considered before a critical summary is offered as a conclusion.
  •  4
    The Lark and the Tortoise
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 19 (1): 89-94. 1989.
  •  31
    The Heuristic Bent
    Philosophy and Rhetoric 26 (1). 1993.
    The logic of questions is still very limited; there is a need for a specification of what is a problem, and what is a problem-situation — or what is an adequate solution to a problem in a given situation. A problem may seek its wording, and so may do the adequacy conditions or desiderata for its solution. For the inarticulate, there is no distinction between theoretical and practical problems. Their problem is a goal, the situation is the available routes to it, and no adequac y conditions.
  •  64
    The methodology of research projects: A sketch
    Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 8 (1): 30-38. 1977.
    Summary There is a traditional reluctance among methodologists to study the ever increasingly important phenomenon of research-projects, research-project evaluations, etc. The reason for this is that projects are embedded in programs and programs in intellectual frameworks, or conceptual frameworks, or metaphysical systems. It sounds dogmatic to judge the product of research by a reference to a metaphysical system. Yet, first of all, it is not so dogmatic if judgment can go both ways, if we have…Read more
  • The Legitimation of Science
    Diálogos. Revista de Filosofía de la Universidad de Puerto Rico 15 (35): 27. 1980.
  •  78
    The last refuge of the scoundrel
    Philosophia 4 (2-3): 315-317. 1974.
    Patriotism is a form of loyalty. The range of loyalty is from patriotism to friendship. Liberals were often accused of having no sense of loyalty. They usually tend to deny the charge — even while refusing to take a loyalty oath. Even the liberal philosopher Sir Karl Popper has claimed (Open Society, i, ch. 10), that liberals can be better patriots than others. 1 find this line of defense erroneous and morally wrong. I find it much nicer, much more honest, to join Martin Buber in his taki…Read more
  •  92
    The Lakatosian revolution
    In R. S. Cohen, P. K. Feyerabend & M. Wartofsky (eds.), Essays in Memory of Imre Lakatos, Reidel. pp. 9--21. 1976.
  •  28
    the walls of the academy. The wall is defended by the idea that not only do experts possess knowledge beyond the ken of lay people, which is trivially true, but that there is an unbridgeable gulf between the two. The aim of this presentation, then, is to discuss the possibility of building a bridge between the ordinary educated citizen and the expert. The tool for this is the famous effort to disseminate scientific literacy, or more generally, any specific sophisticated literacy. The subject-mat…Read more
  •  17
    The Limited Rationality of Technology
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 49 (2): 160-166. 2019.
    Ingemar Nordin’s Using Knowledge: On the Rationality of Science, Technology, and Medicine is a critical rationalist examination of medicine as a social system, largely science-based, but including quackery. Thus rationality is limited, as befits the author’s fallibilism.
  •  3
    The Future of Berkeley’s Instrumentalism
    International Studies in Philosophy 7 167-178. 1975.
  •  14
    The Inductivist Philosophy
    History and Theory 2 1-3. 1963.
    Bacon's inductivist philosophy of science divides thinkers into the scientific and the prejudiced, using as a standard the up-to-date science textbook. Inductivists regard the history of science as progressing smoothly, from facts rather than from problems, to increasingly general theories, undisturbed by contending scientific schools. Conventionalists regard theories as pigeonholes for classifying facts; history of science is the development of increasingly simple theories, neither true nor fal…Read more
  •  37
    The system of higher education always has a significant place in national political affairs. Politically indifferent academics may legitimately ignore this. Those concerned with the welfare of the system of higher education, however, cannot afford this luxury. Further, intellectuals, including academics, are a significant political factor even when passive. Even were all of them to ignore all politics, including the ever-present political importance of the educational system for national politic…Read more
  •  22
    Thomas Kuhn, "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions" (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 4 (4): 351. 1966.
  •  6
    The logic of consensus and of extremes
    In Fred D'Agostino & I. C. Jarvie (eds.), Freedom and Rationality, Reidel. pp. 3--21. 1989.
  •  8
    The Inductivist Techniques
    History and Theory 2 14-20. 1963.
  •  29
    The legacy of Lakatos
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 9 (3): 316-326. 1979.
  •  2
    The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science
    International Studies in Philosophy 34 (4): 168-170. 2002.
  •  7
    Towards Honest Public Relations of Science
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 49 39-58. 1996.
  •  4
    The Disorder of Things (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 32 (2): 136-138. 2000.
  • The Intellectual by Steve Fuller
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 36 (2): 241. 2006.
  •  9
    The Consolations of Science
    American Philosophical Quarterly 23 (2). 1986.
  •  10
    This volume is a historical anthology of interesting views on science from antiquity to the twentieth century plus a defensive anthology of logical positivism, whose legacy deserves better: clear-eyed assessment and then putting to rest.