Joseph Agassi

York University
D'Annunzio University of Chieti–Pescara
  •  40
    Toward a Fictionless Liberalism
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 46 (1): 77-91. 2016.
    This Companion centers on the fictitious social contract that can be used to justify liberalism. As justification, the theory of the contract either fully justifies a regime as liberal or it fully condemns it as illiberal. This conflicts with the common recognition that liberalism is a matter of degree. John Rawls is taken as the leading light; yet at best the Companion manages to picture him as well-intended but hopelessly confusing.
  •  76
    Testing as a bootstrap operation in physics
    Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 4 (1): 1-24. 1973.
    Science uses its firmest conclusions to arrive at new ones which may well completely destroy these, previously firmest, conclusions. The perceptive may notice that when the previously firmest conclusions are demolished we may remain in the dark with no conclusion worth replacing it with. But only when we replace it with a firmer conclusion can we speak of a bootstrap operation rather than of a refutations. Often, to conclude, the ad hoc nature of a fact-like statement is rooted in the theoretica…Read more
  •  13
    Shapin on Boyle
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 27 (2): 219-236. 1997.
  • Second Reply to Professor Feuer
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 7 (3): 263. 1977.
  • Science in Flux
    Erkenntnis 12 (3): 381-398. 1978.
  •  35
    Summary of AFOS workshop, 1994
    Foundations of Science 1 (1): 161-166. 1995.
  •  75
    Sociologism in philosophy of science
    Metaphilosophy 3 (2). 1972.
    SummaryIn a nutshell, the present essay claims this: First, the classical problem of knowledge has recently shifted from, How do I know? to, How do we know?–from psychology to sociology. As a phenomenological matter this is a great improvement, as a solution to the problem of rationality it is erroneous and immoral. The problem, should I act, believe, etc., this or that? is answered: You should do so on the authority of your reason. But change the problem of rationality in accord with the change…Read more
  •  48
    Science in flux
    D. Reidel Pub. Co.. 1975.
    Joseph Agassi is a critic, a gadfly, a debunker and deflater; he is also a constructor, a speculator and an imaginative scholaro In the history and philosophy of science, he has been Peck's bad boy, delighting in sharp and pungent criticism, relishing directness and simplicity, and enjoying it all enormously. As one of that small group of Popper's students (ineluding Bartley, Feyerabend and Lakatos) who took Popper seriously enough to criticize him, Agassi remained his own man, holding Popper's …Read more
  •  7
    Science in Flux
    Philosophical Quarterly 28 (113): 368-369. 1978.
  • Science and Society Studies in the Sociology of Science /Joseph Agassi. --. --
    D. Reidel Pub. Co. Sold and Distributed in the U.S.A. And Canada by Kluwer Boston Inc., C1981. 1981.
  •  71
    Sexism in science
    with Judith Buber Agassi
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 17 (4): 515-522. 1987.
  •  694
    Sensationalism
    Mind 75 (297): 1-24. 1966.
  •  16
  •  11
    Rationality: the critical view (edited book)
    with I. C. Jarvie
    Distributors for the U.S. and Canada, Kluwer Academic Publishers. 1987.
    In our papers on the rationality of magic, we distinghuished, for purposes of analysis, three levels of rationality. First and lowest (rationalitYl) the goal directed action of an agent with given aims and circumstances, where among his circumstances we included his knowledge and opinions. On this level the magician's treatment of illness by incantation is as rational as any traditional doctor's blood-letting or any modern one's use of anti-biotics. At the second level (rationalitY2) we add the …Read more
  •  31
    Simulation?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 4 (4): 535-536. 1981.
  •  24
    Science as commodities
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 40 (1): 154-171. 2010.
    The paucity of literature on the economics of science renders this book valuable. Also, it includes a few interesting papers. Education and research may become more efficient, and their economic aspects want explanations. The explanations may offer suggestion for improvements. The discussions here are mostly unserious and the serious ones are not far-reaching.They concern patent laws more than seems reasonable and ignore many economic aspects of science, mainly its poor communication systems, in…Read more
  •  12
    On Hugo Bergman's Contribution to Epistemology
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 24 (1): 47-58. 1985.
    Approximationism — science approximates the truth as an ideal — is the view of science implicit in all of Einstein's major works, heralded by Hugo Bergman in Hebrew in 1940 and expressed by Karl Popper in 1954 and 1956. Yet Bergman was not sufficiently clear about it, and even Popper is not - as shown by their not giving up certain remnants of the older views which approximationism replaces, even when these remnants are inconsistent with approximationism. Norare the approximationist theories of …Read more
  • Rationalizing the Historiography of Science
    Nuova Civiltà Delle Macchine 25 (2). 2007.
  •  27
    Rationality: Philosophical and social aspects (review)
    Minerva 30 (3): 366-390. 1992.
  •  27
    is an unusual phenomenon. The concern with rights different citizens have in different societies is legal rather than philosophical. It is frequently somewhat a technical matter for jurisprudence to decide exactly what rights a citizen has in a given situation and how he might best exercise his rights. Often, to be sure, the legal technicalities involve matters of principle, and if so these should be made explicit. For this, too, there is a need less for philosophy and more for jurisprudence, fo…Read more
  • Russell Kahl , "Studies in Explanation" (review)
    Philosophical Forum 23 (n/a): 49. 1965.